Hero Circle Shape
Hero Moon Shape
Hero Right Shape
tokenpocket安卓版下载|ethics and morality

tokenpocket安卓版下载|ethics and morality

  • 作者: tokenpocket安卓版下载
  • 2024-03-13 03:20:20

Ethics vs. Morals: What's the Difference?

Ethics vs. Morals: What's the Difference?

Menu

Conditions A-Z

Addiction

Depression

ADHD

Anxiety

Bipolar Disorder

PTSD

View All

Therapy

Therapy Center

When To See a Therapist

Types of Therapy

Best Online Therapy

Best Couples Therapy

Best Family Therapy

View All

Living Well

Managing Stress

Meditation

Sleep and Dreaming

Understanding Emotions

Self-Improvement

Relationships

Healthy Relationships

Dating

Intimacy

Psychology

Theories

Student Resources

Personality Types

Trending

Verywell Mind Insights

2023 Verywell Mind 25

Mental Health in the Classroom

About Us

Editorial Process

Meet Our Review Board

Crisis Support

Search

Search

Clear

GO

Conditions A-Z

Addiction

Depression

ADHD

Anxiety

Bipolar Disorder

PTSD

View All

Therapy

Therapy Center

When To See a Therapist

Types of Therapy

Best Online Therapy

Best Couples Therapy

Best Family Therapy

View All

Living Well

Managing Stress

Meditation

Sleep and Dreaming

Understanding Emotions

Self-Improvement

View All

Relationships

Healthy Relationships

Dating

Intimacy

View All

Psychology

Theories

Student Resources

Personality Types

View All

Trending

Verywell Mind Insights

2023 Verywell Mind 25

Mental Health in the Classroom

View All

More in Theories

Behavioral Psychology

Cognitive Psychology

Developmental Psychology

Personality Psychology

Social Psychology

Biological Psychology

Psychosocial Psychology

View More

About Us

Editorial Process

Privacy Policy

Contact Us

Verywell Mind's content is for informational and educational purposes only. Our website is not intended to be a substitute for professional medical advice, diagnosis, or treatment.

Ⓒ 2024 Dotdash Media, Inc. — All rights reserved

Theories

The Difference Between Morals and Ethics

By

Brittany Loggins

Brittany Loggins

Brittany is a health and lifestyle writer and former staffer at TODAY on NBC and CBS News. She's also contributed to dozens of magazines.

Learn about our

editorial process

Updated on March 20, 2023

Reviewed

Verywell Mind articles are reviewed by mental health professionals. Reviewers confirm the content is thorough and accurate, reflecting the latest evidence-based research. Content is reviewed before publication and upon substantial updates. Learn more.

by

Steven Gans, MD

Reviewed by

Steven Gans, MD

Steven Gans, MD is board-certified in psychiatry and is an active supervisor, teacher, and mentor at Massachusetts General Hospital.

Learn about our

Review Board

Print

Stockarm / Getty Images

Table of Contents

View All

Table of Contents

What Is Morality?

What Are Ethics?

Ethics, Morals, and Mental Health

Are Ethics and Morals Relative?

Discovering Your Own Ethics and Morals

Frequently Asked Questions

Trending Videos

Close this video player

Are ethics vs. morals really just the same thing? It's not uncommon to hear morality and ethics referenced in the same sentence. That said, they are two different things. While they definitely have a lot of commonalities (not to mention very similar definitions!), there are some distinct differences.

Below, we'll outline the difference between morals and ethics, why it matters, and how these two words play into daily life.

What Is Morality?

Morality is a person or society's idea of what is right or wrong, especially in regard to a person's behavior.

Maintaining this type of behavior allows people to live successfully in groups and society. That said, they require a personal adherence to the commitment of the greater good.

Morals have changed over time and based on location. For example, different countries can have different standards of morality. That said, researchers have determined that seven morals seem to transcend across the globe and across time:

Bravery: Bravery has historically helped people determine hierarchies. People who demonstrate the ability to be brave in tough situations have historically been seen as leaders.

Fairness: Think of terms like "meet in the middle" and the concept of taking turns.

Defer to authority: Deferring to authority is important because it signifies that people will adhere to rules that attend to the greater good. This is necessary for a functioning society.

Helping the group: Traditions exist to help us feel closer to our group. This way, you feel more supported, and a general sense of altruism is promoted.

Loving your family: This is a more focused version of helping your group. It's the idea that loving and supporting your family allows you to raise people who will continue to uphold moral norms.

Returning favors: This goes for society as a whole and specifies that people may avoid behaviors that aren't generally altruistic.

Respecting others’ property: This goes back to settling disputes based on prior possession, which also ties in the idea of fairness.

Many of these seven morals require deferring short-term interests for the sake of the larger group. People who act purely out of self-interest can often be regarded as immoral or selfish.

What Is Objective Morality?

What Are Ethics?

Many scholars and researchers don't differentiate between morals and ethics, and that's because they're very similar. Many definitions even explain ethics as a set of moral principles.

The big difference when it comes to ethics is that it refers to community values more than personal values. Dictionary.com defines the term as a system of values that are "moral" as determined by a community.

In general, morals are considered guidelines that affect individuals, and ethics are considered guideposts for entire larger groups or communities. Ethics are also more culturally based than morals.

For example, the seven morals listed earlier transcend cultures, but there are certain rules, especially those in predominantly religious nations, that are determined by cultures that are not recognized around the world.

It's also common to hear the word ethics in medical communities or as the guidepost for other professions that impact larger groups.

For example, the Hippocratic Oath in medicine is an example of a largely accepted ethical practice. The American Medical Association even outlines nine distinct principles that are specified in medical settings. These include putting the patient's care above all else and promoting good health within communities.

Ethics, Morals, and Mental Health

Since morality and ethics can impact individuals and differ from community to community, research has aimed to integrate ethical principles into the practice of psychiatry.

That said, many people grow up adhering to a certain moral or ethical code within their families or communities. When your morals change over time, you might feel a sense of guilt and shame.

For example, many older people still believe that living with a significant other before marriage is immoral. This belief is dated and mostly unrecognized by younger generations, who often see living together as an important and even necessary step in a relationship that helps them make decisions about the future. Additionally, in many cities, living costs are too high for some people to live alone.

However, even if younger person understands that it's not wrong to live with their partner before marriage they might still feel guilty for doing so, especially if they were taught that doing so was immoral.

When dealing with guilt or shame, it's important to assess these feelings with a therapist or someone else that you trust.

Are Ethics and Morals Relative?

Morality is certainly relative since it is determined individually from person to person. In addition, morals can be heavily influenced by families and even religious beliefs, as well as past experiences.

Ethics are relative to different communities and cultures. For example, the ethical guidelines for the medical community don't really have an impact on the people outside of that community. That said, these ethics are still important as they promote caring for the community as a whole.

Discovering Your Own Ethics and Morals

This is important for young adults trying to figure out what values they want to carry into their own lives and future families. This can also determine how well young people create and stick to boundaries in their personal relationships.

Part of determining your individual moral code will involve overcoming feelings of guilt because it may differ from your upbringing. This doesn't mean that you're disrespecting your family, but rather that you're evolving.

Working with a therapist can help you better understand the moral code you want to adhere to and how it ties in aspects of your past and present understanding of the world.

A Word From Verywell

Understanding the difference between ethics vs. morals isn't always cut and dry. And it's OK if your moral and ethical codes don't directly align with the things you learned as a child. Part of growing up and finding autonomy in life involves learning to think for yourself. You determine what you will and will not allow in your life, and what boundaries are acceptable for you in your relationships.

That said, don't feel bad if your ideas of right and wrong change over time. This is a good thing that shows that you are willing to learn and understand those with differing ideas and opinions.

Working with a therapist could prove to be beneficial as you sort out what you do and find to be acceptable parts of your own personal moral code.

Frequently Asked Questions

What is the difference between ethics and morals?

Morals refer to a sense of right or wrong. Ethics, on the other hand, refer more to principles of "good" versus "evil" that are generally agreed upon by a community. 

What are examples of morals and ethics?

Examples of morals can include things such as not lying, being generous, being patient, and being loyal. Examples of ethics can include the ideals of honesty, integrity, respect, and loyalty.

Can a person be moral but not ethical?

Because morals involve a personal code of conduct, it is possible for people to be moral but not ethical. A person can follow their personal moral code without adhering to a more community-based sense of ethical standards. In some cases, a persons individual morals may be at odds with society's ethics.

4 Sources

Verywell Mind uses only high-quality sources, including peer-reviewed studies, to support the facts within our articles. Read our editorial process to learn more about how we fact-check and keep our content accurate, reliable, and trustworthy.

Dictionary.com. Morality.

Curry OS, Mullins DA, Whitehouse H. Is it good to cooperate? Testing the theory of morality-as-cooperation in 60 societies. Current Anthropology. 2019;60(1):47-69. doi:10.1086/701478

Dictionary.com. Ethics.

Crowden A. Ethically Sensitive Mental Health Care: Is there a Need for a Unique Ethics for Psychiatry? Australian & New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry. 2003;37(2):143-149.

By Brittany Loggins

Brittany is a health and lifestyle writer and former staffer at TODAY on NBC and CBS News. She's also contributed to dozens of magazines.

See Our Editorial Process

Meet Our Review Board

Share Feedback

Was this page helpful?

Thanks for your feedback!

What is your feedback?

Helpful

Report an Error

Other

Submit

Related Articles

What Is Morality?

Types of Moral Principles and Examples of Each

Understanding ‘Family of Origin’ Work in Therapy

Hofstede's Six Cultural Dimensions—and Why They Matter

What Is Objective Morality?

How Sexual Repression Can Impact Your Life

Conscious vs. Conscience: What's the Difference?

Character and Personality Are Actually Two Different Things—Here's Why

Kohlberg's Theory of Moral Development

The Psychology of Conflict Theory: A Comprehensive Guide

What Are Conspiracy Theories?

Online Therapy: Security, Ethics, and Legal Issues

Gilligan's Theory of Moral Development

How to Manifest What You Really Want in Your Life

How Internalized Homophobia Impacts Mental Health

Is ADHD Hereditary?

Daily Tips for a Healthy Mind to Your Inbox

Sign Up

You're in!

Thank you, {{form.email}}, for signing up.

There was an error. Please try again.

Conditions A-Z

Therapy

Living Well

Relationships

Psychology

Trending

Meet Our Review Board

About Us

Editorial Process

Diversity Pledge

Privacy Policy

In the News

Advertise

Terms of Service

Careers

Contact

Crisis Support

Follow Us

Verywell Mind's content is for informational and educational purposes only. Our website is not intended to be a substitute for professional medical advice, diagnosis, or treatment.

Ⓒ 2024 Dotdash Media, Inc. — All rights reserved

Verywell Mind is part of the Dotdash Meredith publishing family.

What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics? | Britannica

What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics? | Britannica

Search Britannica

Click here to search

Search Britannica

Click here to search

Login

Subscribe

Subscribe

Home

Games & Quizzes

History & Society

Science & Tech

Biographies

Animals & Nature

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Money

Videos

On This Day

One Good Fact

Dictionary

New Articles

History & Society

Lifestyles & Social Issues

Philosophy & Religion

Politics, Law & Government

World History

Science & Tech

Health & Medicine

Science

Technology

Biographies

Browse Biographies

Animals & Nature

Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates

Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates

Environment

Fossils & Geologic Time

Mammals

Plants

Geography & Travel

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Entertainment & Pop Culture

Literature

Sports & Recreation

Visual Arts

Companions

Demystified

Image Galleries

Infographics

Lists

Podcasts

Spotlights

Summaries

The Forum

Top Questions

#WTFact

100 Women

Britannica Kids

Saving Earth

Space Next 50

Student Center

Home

Games & Quizzes

History & Society

Science & Tech

Biographies

Animals & Nature

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Money

Videos

Discover

Is virtue signalling a perversion of morality?

History of Christianity Quiz

The ABCs of Poetry: Fact or Fiction?

What is ethical animal research? A scientist and veterinarian explain

World Poetry Day

Who Said It? Famous Quotes Quiz

Poetry: First Lines

7 Famous Child Prodigies

Titanosaurs: 8 of the World's Biggest Dinosaurs

12 Greek Gods and Goddesses

Periods of American Literature

Have Any U.S. Presidents Decided Not to Run For a Second Term?

What’s the Difference Between Bison and Buffalo?

7 Deadliest Weapons in History

Home

Demystified

Philosophy & Religion

History & Society

Actions

Cite

verifiedCite

While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies.

Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.

Select Citation Style

MLA

APA

Chicago Manual of Style

Copy Citation

Share

Share

Share to social media

Facebook

Twitter

URL

https://www.britannica.com/story/whats-the-difference-between-morality-and-ethics

What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics?

Cite

verifiedCite

While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies.

Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.

Select Citation Style

MLA

APA

Chicago Manual of Style

Copy Citation

Share

Share

Share to social media

Facebook

Twitter

URL

https://www.britannica.com/story/whats-the-difference-between-morality-and-ethics

Written by

Cydney Grannan

Cydney Grannan was an Editorial Intern at Encyclopædia Britannica. She received her B.A. in English from the University of Chicago in 2016.

Cydney Grannan

Fact-checked by

The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica

Encyclopaedia Britannica's editors oversee subject areas in which they have extensive knowledge, whether from years of experience gained by working on that content or via study for an advanced degree. They write new content and verify and edit content received from contributors.

The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica

© Anatoli Styf/Shutterstock.com Generally, the terms ethics and morality are used interchangeably, although a few different communities (academic, legal, or religious, for example) will occasionally make a distinction. In fact, Britannica’s article on ethics considers the terms to be the same as moral philosophy. While understanding that most ethicists (that is, philosophers who study ethics) consider the terms interchangeable, let’s go ahead and dive into these distinctions. (Read Peter Singer's Britannica entry on ethics.) Both morality and ethics loosely have to do with distinguishing the difference between “good and bad” or “right and wrong.” Many people think of morality as something that’s personal and normative, whereas ethics is the standards of “good and bad” distinguished by a certain community or social setting. For example, your local community may think adultery is immoral, and you personally may agree with that. However, the distinction can be useful if your local community has no strong feelings about adultery, but you consider adultery immoral on a personal level. By these definitions of the terms, your morality would contradict the ethics of your community. In popular discourse, however, we’ll often use the terms moral and immoral when talking about issues like adultery regardless of whether it’s being discussed in a personal or in a community-based situation. As you can see, the distinction can get a bit tricky. It’s important to consider how the two terms have been used in discourse in different fields so that we can consider the connotations of both terms. For example, morality has a Christian connotation to many Westerners, since moral theology is prominent in the church. Similarly, ethics is the term used in conjunction with business, medicine, or law. In these cases, ethics serves as a personal code of conduct for people working in those fields, and the ethics themselves are often highly debated and contentious. These connotations have helped guide the distinctions between morality and ethics. Ethicists today, however, use the terms interchangeably. If they do want to differentiate morality from ethics, the onus is on the ethicist to state the definitions of both terms. Ultimately, the distinction between the two is as substantial as a line drawn in the sand.

Load More

Ethics and Morality | Psychology Today

Ethics and Morality | Psychology Today

Skip to main content

Mobile Navigation

Psychology Today

Find a Therapist

Find a Therapist

Therapists

Therapists

Psychiatrists

Treatment Centers

Support Groups

x

Therapists

:

Login

|

Sign Up

United States

Austin, TX

Brooklyn, NY

Chicago, IL

Denver, CO

Houston, TX

Los Angeles, CA

New York, NY

Portland, OR

San Diego, CA

San Francisco, CA

Seattle, WA

Washington, DC

Atlanta, GA

Sacramento, CA

Get Help

Mental Health

Addiction

Anxiety

ADHD

Asperger's

Autism

Bipolar Disorder

Chronic Pain

Depression

Eating Disorders

Personality

Passive Aggression

Personality

Shyness

Personal Growth

Goal Setting

Happiness

Positive Psychology

Stopping Smoking

Relationships

Low Sexual Desire

Relationships

Sex

Family Life

Child Development

Parenting

View Help Index

Do I Need Help?

Self Tests

Therapy Center NEW

Recently Diagnosed?

Diagnosis Dictionary

Types of Therapy

Talk to Someone

Find a Therapist

Find a Treatment Center

Find a Psychiatrist

Find a Support Group

Find Teletherapy

Magazine

Current

March 2024

The Art of Emotional Intelligence

Understanding what emotional intelligence looks like and the steps needed to improve it could light a path to a more emotionally adept world.

Subscribe

Recent

Issue Archive

Today

News

Essential Reads

Trending Topics

Coronavirus Disease 2019

Narcissism

Dementia

Bias

Affective Forecasting

Neuroscience

See All

us

Search

Search

Search

Verified by Psychology Today

Ethics and Morality

Morality, Ethics, Evil, Greed

Reviewed by Psychology Today Staff

To put it simply, ethics represents the moral code that guides a person’s choices and behaviors throughout their life. The idea of a moral code extends beyond the individual to include what is determined to be right, and wrong, for a community or society at large.

Ethics is concerned with rights, responsibilities, use of language, what it means to live an ethical life, and how people make moral decisions. We may think of moralizing as an intellectual exercise, but more frequently it's an attempt to make sense of our gut instincts and reactions. It's a subjective concept, and many people have strong and stubborn beliefs about what's right and wrong that can place them in direct contrast to the moral beliefs of others. Yet even though morals may vary from person to person, religion to religion, and culture to culture, many have been found to be universal, stemming from basic human emotions.

Contents

The Science of Being Virtuous

Understanding Amorality

The Stages of Moral Development

The Science of Being Virtuous

Those who are considered morally good are said to be virtuous, holding themselves to high ethical standards, while those viewed as morally bad are thought of as wicked, sinful, or even criminal. Morality was a key concern of Aristotle, who first studied questions such as “What is moral responsibility?” and “What does it take for a human being to be virtuous?”

Are people born with morals and ethics?

Created with Sketch.

We used to think that people are born with a blank slate, but research has shown that people have an innate sense of morality. Of course, parents and the greater society can certainly nurture and develop morality and ethics in children.

Can you have morals without religion?

Created with Sketch.

Humans are ethical and moral regardless of religion and God. People are not fundamentally good nor are they fundamentally evil. However, a Pew study found that atheists are much less likely than theists to believe that there are "absolute standards of right and wrong." In effect, atheism does not undermine morality, but the atheist’s conception of morality may depart from that of the traditional theist.

Do animals have morals?

Created with Sketch.

Animals are like humans—and humans are animals, after all. Many studies have been conducted across animal species, and more than 90 percent of their behavior is what can be identified as “prosocial” or positive. Plus, you won’t find mass warfare in animals as you do in humans. Hence, in a way, you can say that animals are more moral than humans.

What is the difference between moral psychology and moral philosophy?

Created with Sketch.

The examination of moral psychology involves the study of moral philosophy but the field is more concerned with how a person comes to make a right or wrong decision, rather than what sort of decisions he or she should have made. Character, reasoning, responsibility, and altruism, among other areas, also come into play, as does the development of morality.

article continues after advertisement

Understanding Amorality

The seven deadly sins were first enumerated in the sixth century by Pope Gregory I, and represent the sweep of immoral behavior. Also known as the cardinal sins or seven deadly vices, they are vanity, jealousy, anger, laziness, greed, gluttony, and lust. People who demonstrate these immoral behaviors are often said to be flawed in character. Some modern thinkers suggest that virtue often disguises a hidden vice; it just depends on where we tip the scale.

What is the difference between being amoral and being immoral?

Created with Sketch.

An amoral person has no sense of, or care for, what is right or wrong. There is no regard for either morality or immorality. Conversely, an immoral person knows the difference, yet he does the wrong thing, regardless. The amoral politician, for example, has no conscience and makes choices based on his own personal needs; he is oblivious to whether his actions are right or wrong.

What is amoral behavior?

Created with Sketch.

One could argue that the actions of Wells Fargo, for example, were amoral if the bank had no sense of right or wrong. In the 2016 fraud scandal, the bank created fraudulent savings and checking accounts for millions of clients, unbeknownst to them. Of course, if the bank knew what it was doing all along, then the scandal would be labeled immoral.

Why do some people lie a lot?

Created with Sketch.

Everyone tells white lies to a degree, and often the lie is done for the greater good. But the idea that a small percentage of people tell the lion’s share of lies is the Pareto principle, the law of the vital few. It is 20 percent of the population that accounts for 80 percent of a behavior.

Do people know what’s right from wrong?

Created with Sketch.

We do know what is right from wrong. If you harm and injure another person, that is wrong. However, what is right for one person, may well be wrong for another. A good example of this dichotomy is the religious conservative who thinks that a woman’s right to her body is morally wrong. In this case, one’s ethics are based on one’s values; and the moral divide between values can be vast.

The Stages of Moral Development

Psychologist Lawrence Kohlberg established his stages of moral development in 1958. This framework has led to current research into moral psychology. Kohlberg's work addresses the process of how we think of right and wrong and is based on Jean Piaget's theory of moral judgment for children. His stages include pre-conventional, conventional, post-conventional, and what we learn in one stage is integrated into the subsequent stages.

What is the Pre-Conventional Stage?

Created with Sketch.

The pre-conventional stage is driven by obedience and punishment. This is a child's view of what is right or wrong. Examples of this thinking: “I hit my brother and I received a time-out.” “How can I avoid punishment?” “What's in it for me?” 

What is the Conventional Stage?

Created with Sketch.

The conventional stage is when we accept societal views on rights and wrongs. In this stage people follow rules with a good boy and nice girl orientation. An example of this thinking: “Do it for me.” This stage also includes law-and-order morality: “Do your duty.”

What is the Post-Conventional Stage?

Created with Sketch.

The post-conventional stage is more abstract: “Your right and wrong is not my right and wrong.” This stage goes beyond social norms and an individual develops his own moral compass, sticking to personal principles of what is ethical or not.

Essential Reads

Archetypal Psychopaths in Two Contemporary Films

The film "Killers of the Flower Moon" and "A Zone of Interest" are stories of widespread murder fuelled by genocidal racism, and greed perpetrated by two types of psychopaths.

Key Principles for Interpreting Dreams with AI

Common guidelines for sharing and interpreting dreams between people can be applied to AI systems, too. No need for reinventing the ethical wheel.

What Primitive, Ancient Animals Can Teach Us About Being Human

As our understanding of animal intelligence deepens, society faces ethical dilemmas regarding the treatment and rights of even the simplest non-human animals.

The Debate Over Psychiatric Suffering and Physician-Assisted Death

In some locales, it is legal for doctors to assist in the deaths of people suffering with psychiatric illnesses. There are, however, many concerns regarding the practice.

Making Up to Make the Grade

How appearance anxiety is affecting the mental health of young women and girls.

How appearance anxiety is affecting the mental health of young women and girls.

The Mystic Chords of Memory

Aromas and flavors switch on a neural wayback machine that accesses deep recollection.

Aromas and flavors switch on a neural wayback machine that accesses deep recollection.

Why You Might Cut Off Your Nose to Spite Your Face

Spite often drives punishment. The problem, researchers find, is that it's not always worth the benefit; it often leads us into excessive self-sacrifice.

Spite often drives punishment. The problem, researchers find, is that it's not always worth the benefit; it often leads us into excessive self-sacrifice.

Eight Simple Ways to Bully-Proof Your Healthy Conscience

Your biggest vulnerability to bullying is your active healthy conscience. Here's how to maintain it without being bullied by shameless moralizing scolds.

Your biggest vulnerability to bullying is your active healthy conscience. Here's how to maintain it without being bullied by shameless moralizing scolds.

Coping With the Loss of Your Reproductive Rights

The Alabama ruling has sent shockwaves throughout the infertility community. During times of uncertainty, prioritize your mental health and assemble a toolkit of coping strategies.

The Alabama ruling has sent shockwaves throughout the infertility community. During times of uncertainty, prioritize your mental health and assemble a toolkit of coping strategies.

Existential Therapy for Existential Times

The revival of Existential Therapy is imperative today; the crises we face are emotional, relational, and spiritual.

The revival of Existential Therapy is imperative today; the crises we face are emotional, relational, and spiritual.

What Is Your Therapist Thinking?

During your session, your therapist may be tuning into 13 inner voices. Here's a look inside their head.

During your session, your therapist may be tuning into 13 inner voices. Here's a look inside their head.

Unconscious Memory Updating

Our political identity is quite fluid, subject to the vagaries of time and memory. It updates and reforms itself in unpredictable ways.

Our political identity is quite fluid, subject to the vagaries of time and memory. It updates and reforms itself in unpredictable ways.

ChatGPT’s Recipe for Dog Meat

Personal Perspective: What can we learn about our own psychology from how ChatGPT responds to requests for dog meat recipes and pig meat recipes.

Personal Perspective: What can we learn about our own psychology from how ChatGPT responds to requests for dog meat recipes and pig meat recipes.

Becoming Gandhi: A Writer's Search for a Moral Life

Veteran journalist Perry Garfinkel undertook a fascinating experiment at a low point in his life: to live by Gandhi's moral precepts for a year and see what happens.

Veteran journalist Perry Garfinkel undertook a fascinating experiment at a low point in his life: to live by Gandhi's moral precepts for a year and see what happens.

1

2

Next

Ethics and Morality Resources

Get Help

Find a therapist near me

City or Zip

Connected Topics

Philosophy

Deception

Altruism

Moral Injury

Test Yourself

Egoism vs. Altruism

Most Popular

advertisement

Find a Therapist

Get the help you need from a therapist near you–a FREE service from Psychology Today.

City or Zip

Cities:

Atlanta, GA

Austin, TX

Baltimore, MD

Boston, MA

Brooklyn, NY

Charlotte, NC

Chicago, IL

Columbus, OH

Dallas, TX

Denver, CO

Detroit, MI

Houston, TX

Indianapolis, IN

Jacksonville, FL

Las Vegas, NV

Los Angeles, CA

Louisville, KY

Memphis, TN

Miami, FL

Milwaukee, WI

Minneapolis, MN

Nashville, TN

New York, NY

Oakland, CA

Omaha, NE

Philadelphia, PA

Phoenix, AZ

Pittsburgh, PA

Portland, OR

Raleigh, NC

Sacramento, CA

Saint Louis, MO

San Antonio, TX

San Diego, CA

San Francisco, CA

San Jose, CA

Seattle, WA

Tucson, AZ

Washington, DC

Are you a Therapist?

Get Listed Today

advertisement

Psychology Today

Recent Issues

Subscribe Today

About

Editorial Process

Privacy

Terms

Accessibility

United States

Psychology Today © 2024 Sussex Publishers, LLC

Back

Psychology Today

Home

Find a Therapist

Get Help

Magazine

Today

Back

Find a Therapist

Get Help

Find a Therapist

Find a Treatment Center

Find a Psychiatrist

Find a Support Group

Find Teletherapy

Members

Login

Sign Up

United States

Austin, TX

Brooklyn, NY

Chicago, IL

Denver, CO

Houston, TX

Los Angeles, CA

New York, NY

Portland, OR

San Diego, CA

San Francisco, CA

Seattle, WA

Washington, DC

Back

Get Help

Mental Health

Addiction

Anxiety

ADHD

Asperger's

Autism

Bipolar Disorder

Chronic Pain

Depression

Eating Disorders

Personality

Passive Aggression

Personality

Shyness

Personal Growth

Goal Setting

Happiness

Positive Psychology

Stopping Smoking

Relationships

Low Sexual Desire

Relationships

Sex

Family Life

Child Development

Parenting

View Help Index

Do I Need Help?

Self Tests

Therapy Center NEW

Recently Diagnosed?

Diagnosis Dictionary

Types of Therapy

Talk to Someone

Find a Therapist

Find a Treatment Center

Find a Psychiatrist

Find a Support Group

Find Teletherapy

Back

Magazine

March 2024

The Art of Emotional Intelligence

Understanding what emotional intelligence looks like and the steps needed to improve it could light a path to a more emotionally adept world.

Subscribe

Issue Archive

Back

Today

News

Essential Reads

Trending Topics

Coronavirus Disease 2019

Narcissism

Dementia

Bias

Affective Forecasting

Neuroscience

See All

Difference Between Morals and Ethics (with Examples and Comparison Chart) - Key Differences

Difference Between Morals and Ethics (with Examples and Comparison Chart) - Key Differences

Business

Finance

Banking

Education

General

Law

Science

IT

English

Key DifferencesKnow the Differences & Comparisons

Difference Between Morals and Ethics

We greatly encounter moral and ethical issues, in our day to day life. Perhaps, these two defines a personality, attitude, and behavior of a person. The word Morals is derived from a Greek word “Mos” which means custom. On the other hand, if we talk about Ethics, it is also derived from a Greek word “Ethikos” which means character. Put simply, morals are the customs established by group of individuals whereas ethics defines the character of an individual.

While morals are concerned with principles of right and wrong, ethics are related to right and wrong conduct of an individual in a particular sitution. Many use the two terms as synonyms, but there are slight and subtle differences between morals and ethis, which are described in the article below.

Content: Morals Vs Ethics

Comparison Chart

Definition

Key Differences

Video

Examples

Conclusion

Comparison Chart

Basis for ComparisonMoralsEthics

MeaningMorals are the beliefs of the individual or group as to what is right or wrong.Ethics are the guiding principles which help the individual or group to decide what is good or bad.

What is it?General principles set by groupResponse to a specific situation

Root wordMos which means customEthikos which means character

Governed BySocial and cultural normsIndividual or Legal and Professional norms

Deals withPrinciples of right and wrongRight and wrong conduct

Applicability in BusinessNoYes

ConsistencyMorals may differ from society to society and culture to culture.Ethics are generally uniform.

ExpressionMorals are expressed in the form of general rules and statements.Ethics are abstract.

Freedom to think and chooseNoYes

Definition of Morals

Morals are the social, cultural and religious beliefs or values of an individual or group which tells us what is right or wrong. They are the rules and standards made by the society or culture which is to be followed by us while deciding what is right. Some moral principles are:

Do not cheat

Be loyal

Be patient

Always tell the truth

Be generous

Morals refer to the beliefs what is not objectively right, but what is considered right for any situation, so it can be said that what is morally correct may not be objectively correct.

Definition of Ethics

Ethics is a branch of philosophy that deals with the principles of conduct of an individual or group. It works as a guiding principle as to decide what is good or bad. They are the standards which govern the life of a person. Ethics is also known as moral philosophy. Some ethical principles are:

Truthfulness

Honesty

Loyalty

Respect

Fairness

Integrity

Key Differences Between Morals and Ethics

The major differences between Morals and Ethics are as under:

Morals deal with what is ‘right or wrong’. Ethics deals with what is ‘good or evil’.

Morals are general guidelines framed by the society E.g. We should speak truth. Conversely, ethics are a response to a particular situation, E.g. Is it ethical to state the truth in a particular situation?

The term morals is derived from a Greek word ‘mos’ which refers to custom and the customs are determined by group of individuals or some authority. On the other hand, ethics is originated from Greek word ‘ethikos’ which refers to character and character is an attribute.

Morals are dictated by society, culture or religion while Ethics are chosen by the person himself which governs his life.

Morals  are concerned with principles of right and wrong. On the contrary, ethics stresses on right and wrong conduct.

As morals are framed and designed by the group, there is no option to think and choose; the individual can either accept or reject. Conversely, the people are free to think and choose the principles of his life in ethics.

Morals may vary from society to society and culture to culture. As opposed to Ethics, which remains same regardless of any culture, religion or society.

Morals do not have any applicability to business, whereas Ethics is widely applicable in the business known as business ethics.

Morals are expressed in the form of statements, but Ethics are not expressed in the form of statements.

Video: Morals Vs Ethics

Examples

If the son of a big politician has committed a crime and he uses his powers to free his son from legal consequences. Then this act is immoral because the politician is trying to save a culprit.

A very close friend or relative of an interviewer comes for an interview and without asking a single question, he selects him. This act is unethical because the selection process must be transparent and unbiased.

A grocer sells adulterated products to his customers to earn more profit. This act is neither moral nor ethical because he is cheating his customers and profession at the same time.

Conclusion

Every single individual has some principles which help him throughout his life to cope up with any adverse situation; they are known as ethics. On the other hand, Morals are not the hard and fast rules or very rigid, but they are the rules which a majority of people considered as right. That is why the people widely accept them. This is all for differentiating Morals from Ethics.

You Might Also Like:

Difference Between Ethics and Values

Difference Between Law and Ethics

Difference Between Code of Ethics and Code of Conduct

Difference Between Moral and Morale

Difference Between Personality and Character

Difference Between Culture and Society

Comments

Aivee Akther says

April 7, 2016 at 5:42 pm

wow,,,,perfect

Reply

mobi ktk says

August 28, 2016 at 5:18 pm

easyly understandable

Reply

NKWETI Roland TICHA says

March 4, 2017 at 9:33 pm

thanks for your clarification.

Reply

Surbhi S says

March 6, 2017 at 9:47 am

We really appreciate your views, thanks for sharing.

Reply

Bhakti says

July 7, 2017 at 9:12 am

Thanks for ur help…

Reply

Ekart Mwankenja says

July 14, 2017 at 4:40 am

Thanks

Reply

Khagendra Thapa says

August 7, 2017 at 9:22 pm

Hello:

Thanks for these clear and very comprehensive explanations. These are the best explanations I found. I really appreciate it.

Dr. K. Thapa

Reply

Nathan Laia says

April 23, 2018 at 8:02 am

Thanks a lot. This article is very understandable and very helpful. I do appreciate your work

Reply

Marvin Ekwenugo says

April 30, 2018 at 4:51 pm

Thoroughly differentiated. Clarity came off easily.

Reply

Surbhi S says

May 11, 2018 at 3:28 pm

Thank you all we really value your views, it means a lot to us and motivates us to do even better in future. Keep reading

Reply

Silky says

May 16, 2018 at 2:38 am

Ty …ur answer is good

Reply

sneha yadav says

September 8, 2018 at 9:48 pm

wow ….great explanation…through examples it is more clear.

Reply

ebram says

November 9, 2018 at 12:01 pm

Thanks for your simple explanations. That’s good

Reply

mk says

December 11, 2018 at 4:41 pm

keep it up! medium acts like a good teacher!

Reply

Seán Easton says

January 19, 2019 at 1:32 pm

A very helpful and practical presentation of the concepts.

Reply

Nim says

March 31, 2019 at 12:11 pm

Clearly explained with very good examples. Thank you for sharing this much of an excellent explanation. well done! Keep it up!

Reply

Praja says

April 12, 2019 at 11:24 am

Thanks for the great explanation.

Reply

Kelly Kapelembi says

May 2, 2019 at 11:31 am

Wow, so easy to understand. Excellent piece of writing with good and practical examples.

Reply

saurav says

July 19, 2019 at 4:04 pm

good work and and easily understandable

Reply

DR.KATYETYE says

August 22, 2019 at 9:21 pm

simple but rigid information

well done!!!!!

Reply

Simisola Omotoso says

June 16, 2020 at 5:51 am

This pretty much cleared the two concepts for me. Thank you!

Reply

Nouman aslam says

December 7, 2020 at 2:07 pm

great job, well define, easily understandable, thank you very much!

Reply

JAMES LIIMAN JABONG says

February 8, 2021 at 8:34 pm

wow! so comprehensible, I must say that it really helps me to draw a clear line of dichotomy between the two concepts. God bless you for sharing your knowledge on that.

Reply

Linda says

March 6, 2021 at 9:07 pm

Thank you for a very helpful and informative article.

Reply

Boitumelo Morokeng says

October 14, 2021 at 12:56 pm

Thank you for a very helpful article it helped me on my assignment. Thanks again

Reply

Chi says

October 23, 2021 at 12:53 pm

Thank you so much.

Reply

Charles says

August 10, 2022 at 6:35 am

I enjoyed reading this article. Thank you for sharing this valuable information with us. Keep up the good work and I look forward to reading more of your posts

Reply

Thomas says

August 10, 2022 at 6:41 am

thanka a lot.

Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel replyYour email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *Comment * Name *

Email *

Website

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Top 5 Differences

Difference Between PERT and CPM

Difference Between Micro and Macro Economics

Difference Between Developed Countries and Developing Countries

Difference Between Management and Administration

Difference Between Qualitative and Quantitative Research

New Additions

Difference Between Introduction and Executive Summary

Difference Between Programmed and Non-programmed Decisions

Difference Between Depreciation and Devaluation of Currency

Difference Between Consumer Market and Business Market

Difference Between Manufacturing and Service Operations

Difference Between Currency and Money

Difference Between ACH and Wire Transfer

Difference Between Vowels and Consonants

Difference Between Revising and Editing

Difference Between Who’s and Whose

Categories

Banking

Business

Education

English

Finance

General

IT

Law

Science

Copyright © 2024 · Key Differences · Contact Us · About Us · Privacy

Ethics | Definition, History, Examples, Types, Philosophy, & Facts | Britannica

Ethics | Definition, History, Examples, Types, Philosophy, & Facts | Britannica

Search Britannica

Click here to search

Search Britannica

Click here to search

Login

Subscribe

Subscribe

Home

Games & Quizzes

History & Society

Science & Tech

Biographies

Animals & Nature

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Money

Videos

On This Day

One Good Fact

Dictionary

New Articles

History & Society

Lifestyles & Social Issues

Philosophy & Religion

Politics, Law & Government

World History

Science & Tech

Health & Medicine

Science

Technology

Biographies

Browse Biographies

Animals & Nature

Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates

Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates

Environment

Fossils & Geologic Time

Mammals

Plants

Geography & Travel

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Entertainment & Pop Culture

Literature

Sports & Recreation

Visual Arts

Companions

Demystified

Image Galleries

Infographics

Lists

Podcasts

Spotlights

Summaries

The Forum

Top Questions

#WTFact

100 Women

Britannica Kids

Saving Earth

Space Next 50

Student Center

Home

Games & Quizzes

History & Society

Science & Tech

Biographies

Animals & Nature

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Money

Videos

ethics

Table of Contents

ethics

Table of Contents

Introduction & Top QuestionsThe origins of ethicsMythical accountsIntroduction of moral codesProblems of divine originPrehuman ethicsNonhuman behaviourKinship and reciprocityAnthropology and ethicsThe history of Western ethicsAncient civilizations to the end of the 19th centuryThe ancient Middle East and AsiaThe Middle EastIndiaChinaAncient and Classical GreeceAncient GreeceSocratesPlatoAristotleLater Greek and Roman ethicsThe StoicsThe EpicureansChristian ethics from the New Testament to the ScholasticsEthics in the New TestamentSt. AugustineSt. Thomas Aquinas and the ScholasticsThe Renaissance and the ReformationMachiavelliThe first ProtestantsThe British tradition from Hobbes to the utilitariansHobbesEarly intuitionists: Cudworth, More, and ClarkeShaftesbury and the moral sense schoolButler on self-interest and conscienceThe climax of moral sense theory: Hutcheson and HumeThe intuitionist response: Price and ReidUtilitarianismPaleyBenthamMillSidgwickThe Continental tradition from Spinoza to NietzscheSpinozaLeibnizRousseauKantHegelMarxNietzscheWestern ethics from the beginning of the 20th centuryMetaethicsMoore and the naturalistic fallacyModern intuitionismEmotivismExistentialismUniversal prescriptivismLater developments in metaethicsMoral realismKantian constructivism: a middle ground?Irrealist views: projectivism and expressivismEthics and reasons for actionNormative ethicsThe debate over consequentialismVarieties of consequentialismObjections to consequentialismAn ethics of prima facie dutiesRawls’s theory of justiceRights theoriesNatural law ethicsVirtue ethicsFeminist ethicsEthical egoismApplied ethicsEqualityAnimalsEnvironmental ethicsWar and peaceAbortion, euthanasia, and the value of human lifeBioethics

References & Edit History

Quick Facts & Related Topics

Images

For Students

ethics summary

Related Questions

What is ethics?

How is ethics different from morality?

Why does ethics matter?

Is ethics a social science?

What did Aristotle do?

Read Next

Philosophers to Know, Part I

What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics?

Plato and Aristotle: How Do They Differ?

What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics?

Order in the Court: 10 “Trials of the Century”

Discover

7 Deadliest Weapons in History

Have Any U.S. Presidents Decided Not to Run For a Second Term?

7 Famous Child Prodigies

Nostradamus and His Prophecies

Why Doesn’t Arizona Observe Daylight Saving Time?

Periods of American Literature

How Did Alexander the Great Really Die?

Home

Philosophy & Religion

Ethical Issues

History & Society

ethics

philosophy

Actions

Cite

verifiedCite

While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies.

Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.

Select Citation Style

MLA

APA

Chicago Manual of Style

Copy Citation

Share

Share

Share to social media

Facebook

Twitter

URL

https://www.britannica.com/topic/ethics-philosophy

Give Feedback

External Websites

Feedback

Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).

Feedback Type

Select a type (Required)

Factual Correction

Spelling/Grammar Correction

Link Correction

Additional Information

Other

Your Feedback

Submit Feedback

Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

External Websites

Business LibreTexts - What is Ethics?

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Ethics and Contrastivism

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Empathy and Sympathy in Ethics

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life

Philosophy Basics - Ethics

American Medical Association - Journal of Ethics - Triage and Ethics

Psychology Today - Ethics and Morality

Government of Canada - Treasury Board of Canada Secretariat - What is ethics?

Cornell Law School - Legal Information Institute - Ethics

Britannica Websites

Articles from Britannica Encyclopedias for elementary and high school students.

ethics and morality - Student Encyclopedia (Ages 11 and up)

Print

print

Print

Please select which sections you would like to print:

Table Of Contents

Cite

verifiedCite

While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies.

Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.

Select Citation Style

MLA

APA

Chicago Manual of Style

Copy Citation

Share

Share

Share to social media

Facebook

Twitter

URL

https://www.britannica.com/topic/ethics-philosophy

Feedback

External Websites

Feedback

Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).

Feedback Type

Select a type (Required)

Factual Correction

Spelling/Grammar Correction

Link Correction

Additional Information

Other

Your Feedback

Submit Feedback

Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

External Websites

Business LibreTexts - What is Ethics?

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Ethics and Contrastivism

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Empathy and Sympathy in Ethics

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life

Philosophy Basics - Ethics

American Medical Association - Journal of Ethics - Triage and Ethics

Psychology Today - Ethics and Morality

Government of Canada - Treasury Board of Canada Secretariat - What is ethics?

Cornell Law School - Legal Information Institute - Ethics

Britannica Websites

Articles from Britannica Encyclopedias for elementary and high school students.

ethics and morality - Student Encyclopedia (Ages 11 and up)

Also known as: moral philosophy

Written by

Peter Singer

Peter Singer is the Ira W. DeCamp Professor of Bioethics at the University Center for Human Values, Princeton University. A specialist in applied ethics, he approaches ethical issues from a secular, preference-utilitarian...

Peter Singer

Fact-checked by

The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica

Encyclopaedia Britannica's editors oversee subject areas in which they have extensive knowledge, whether from years of experience gained by working on that content or via study for an advanced degree. They write new content and verify and edit content received from contributors.

The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica

Last Updated:

Feb 14, 2024

Article History

Table of Contents

Code of Hammurabi

See all media

Category:

History & Society

Also called:

moral philosophy

(Show more)

Key People:

Socrates

Aristotle

Plato

St. Augustine

Immanuel Kant

(Show more)

Related Topics:

history of ethics

Trolley problem

legal ethics

biocentrism

optimism

(Show more)

On the Web:

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life (Feb. 14, 2024)

(Show more)

See all related content →

Top Questions

What is ethics?The term ethics may refer to the philosophical study of the concepts of moral right and wrong and moral good and bad, to any philosophical theory of what is morally right and wrong or morally good and bad, and to any system or code of moral rules, principles, or values. The last may be associated with particular religions, cultures, professions, or virtually any other group that is at least partly characterized by its moral outlook.How is ethics different from morality?Traditionally, ethics referred to the philosophical study of morality, the latter being a more or less systematic set of beliefs, usually held in common by a group, about how people should live. Ethics also referred to particular philosophical theories of morality. Later the term was applied to particular (and narrower) moral codes or value systems. Ethics and morality are now used almost interchangeably in many contexts, but the name of the philosophical study remains ethics.Why does ethics matter?Ethics matters because (1) it is part of how many groups define themselves and thus part of the identity of their individual members, (2) other-regarding values in most ethical systems both reflect and foster close human relationships and mutual respect and trust, and (3) it could be “rational” for a self-interested person to be moral, because his or her self-interest is arguably best served in the long run by reciprocating the moral behaviour of others.Is ethics a social science?No. Understood as equivalent to morality, ethics could be studied as a social-psychological or historical phenomenon, but in that case it would be an object of social-scientific study, not a social science in itself. Understood as the philosophical study of moral concepts, ethics is a branch of philosophy, not of social science.ethics, the discipline concerned with what is morally good and bad and morally right and wrong. The term is also applied to any system or theory of moral values or principles.(Read Britannica’s biography of this author, Peter Singer.)How should we live? Shall we aim at happiness or at knowledge, virtue, or the creation of beautiful objects? If we choose happiness, will it be our own or the happiness of all? And what of the more particular questions that face us: is it right to be dishonest in a good cause? Can we justify living in opulence while elsewhere in the world people are starving? Is going to war justified in cases where it is likely that innocent people will be killed? Is it wrong to clone a human being or to destroy human embryos in medical research? What are our obligations, if any, to the generations of humans who will come after us and to the nonhuman animals with whom we share the planet?Ethics deals with such questions at all levels. Its subject consists of the fundamental issues of practical decision making, and its major concerns include the nature of ultimate value and the standards by which human actions can be judged right or wrong.The terms ethics and morality are closely related. It is now common to refer to ethical judgments or to ethical principles where it once would have been more accurate to speak of moral judgments or moral principles. These applications are an extension of the meaning of ethics. In earlier usage, the term referred not to morality itself but to the field of study, or branch of inquiry, that has morality as its subject matter. In this sense, ethics is equivalent to moral philosophy.Although ethics has always been viewed as a branch of philosophy, its all-embracing practical nature links it with many other areas of study, including anthropology, biology, economics, history, politics, sociology, and theology. Yet, ethics remains distinct from such disciplines because it is not a matter of factual knowledge in the way that the sciences and other branches of inquiry are. Rather, it has to do with determining the nature of normative theories and applying these sets of principles to practical moral problems.

Get a Britannica Premium subscription and gain access to exclusive content.

Subscribe Now

This article, then, will deal with ethics as a field of philosophy, especially as it has developed in the West. For coverage of religious conceptions of ethics and the ethical systems associated with world religions, see Buddhism; Christianity; Confucianism; Hinduism; Jainism; Judaism; Sikhism. The origins of ethics Mythical accounts Introduction of moral codes When did ethics begin and how did it originate? If one has in mind ethics proper—i.e., the systematic study of what is morally right and wrong—it is clear that ethics could have come into existence only when human beings started to reflect on the best way to live. This reflective stage emerged long after human societies had developed some kind of morality, usually in the form of customary standards of right and wrong conduct. The process of reflection tended to arise from such customs, even if in the end it may have found them wanting. Accordingly, ethics began with the introduction of the first moral codes. Virtually every human society has some form of myth to explain the origin of morality. In the Louvre in Paris there is a black Babylonian column with a relief showing the sun god Shamash presenting the code of laws to Hammurabi (died c. 1750 bce), known as the Code of Hammurabi. The Hebrew Bible (Old Testament) account of God’s giving the Ten Commandments to Moses (flourished 14th–13th century bce) on Mount Sinai might be considered another example. In the dialogue Protagoras by Plato (428/427–348/347 bce), there is an avowedly mythical account of how Zeus took pity on the hapless humans, who were physically no match for the other beasts. To make up for these deficiencies, Zeus gave humans a moral sense and the capacity for law and justice, so that they could live in larger communities and cooperate with one another. That morality should be invested with all the mystery and power of divine origin is not surprising. Nothing else could provide such strong reasons for accepting the moral law. By attributing a divine origin to morality, the priesthood became its interpreter and guardian and thereby secured for itself a power that it would not readily relinquish. This link between morality and religion has been so firmly forged that it is still sometimes asserted that there can be no morality without religion. According to this view, ethics is not an independent field of study but rather a branch of theology (see moral theology).

There is some difficulty, already known to Plato, with the view that morality was created by a divine power. In his dialogue Euthyphro, Plato considered the suggestion that it is divine approval that makes an action good. Plato pointed out that, if this were the case, one could not say that the gods approve of such actions because they are good. Why then do they approve of them? Is their approval entirely arbitrary? Plato considered this impossible and so held that there must be some standards of right or wrong that are independent of the likes and dislikes of the gods. Modern philosophers have generally accepted Plato’s argument, because the alternative implies that if, for example, the gods had happened to approve of torturing children and to disapprove of helping one’s neighbours, then torture would have been good and neighbourliness bad.

Morality | Definition, Ethics, Comparative Ethics, Ethical Relativism, & Facts | Britannica

Morality | Definition, Ethics, Comparative Ethics, Ethical Relativism, & Facts | Britannica

Search Britannica

Click here to search

Search Britannica

Click here to search

Login

Subscribe

Subscribe

Home

Games & Quizzes

History & Society

Science & Tech

Biographies

Animals & Nature

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Money

Videos

On This Day

One Good Fact

Dictionary

New Articles

History & Society

Lifestyles & Social Issues

Philosophy & Religion

Politics, Law & Government

World History

Science & Tech

Health & Medicine

Science

Technology

Biographies

Browse Biographies

Animals & Nature

Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates

Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates

Environment

Fossils & Geologic Time

Mammals

Plants

Geography & Travel

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Entertainment & Pop Culture

Literature

Sports & Recreation

Visual Arts

Companions

Demystified

Image Galleries

Infographics

Lists

Podcasts

Spotlights

Summaries

The Forum

Top Questions

#WTFact

100 Women

Britannica Kids

Saving Earth

Space Next 50

Student Center

Home

Games & Quizzes

History & Society

Science & Tech

Biographies

Animals & Nature

Geography & Travel

Arts & Culture

Money

Videos

morality

Table of Contents

morality

Table of Contents

Introduction

References & Edit History

Quick Facts & Related Topics

Videos

Read Next

What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics?

Discover

The Largest Islands in the World

7 Puzzling Plane Disappearances

The Seven Sacraments of the Roman Catholic church

Periods of American Literature

7 Famous Child Prodigies

Nostradamus and His Prophecies

Ten Days That Vanished: The Switch to the Gregorian Calendar

Home

Philosophy & Religion

Ethical Issues

History & Society

morality

human behaviour

Actions

Cite

verifiedCite

While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies.

Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.

Select Citation Style

MLA

APA

Chicago Manual of Style

Copy Citation

Share

Share

Share to social media

Facebook

Twitter

URL

https://www.britannica.com/topic/morality

Give Feedback

External Websites

Feedback

Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).

Feedback Type

Select a type (Required)

Factual Correction

Spelling/Grammar Correction

Link Correction

Additional Information

Other

Your Feedback

Submit Feedback

Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

External Websites

Psychology Today - Ethics and Morality

National Center for Biotechnology Information - The Difference of Being Human: Morality

Social Science LibreTexts - The Problem of Morality

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - The Definition of Morality

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life

Print

Cite

verifiedCite

While every effort has been made to follow citation style rules, there may be some discrepancies.

Please refer to the appropriate style manual or other sources if you have any questions.

Select Citation Style

MLA

APA

Chicago Manual of Style

Copy Citation

Share

Share

Share to social media

Facebook

Twitter

URL

https://www.britannica.com/topic/morality

Feedback

External Websites

Feedback

Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires login).

Feedback Type

Select a type (Required)

Factual Correction

Spelling/Grammar Correction

Link Correction

Additional Information

Other

Your Feedback

Submit Feedback

Thank you for your feedback

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

External Websites

Psychology Today - Ethics and Morality

National Center for Biotechnology Information - The Difference of Being Human: Morality

Social Science LibreTexts - The Problem of Morality

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - The Definition of Morality

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life

Also known as: morals

Written and fact-checked by

The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica

Encyclopaedia Britannica's editors oversee subject areas in which they have extensive knowledge, whether from years of experience gained by working on that content or via study for an advanced degree. They write new content and verify and edit content received from contributors.

The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica

Last Updated:

Feb 14, 2024

Article History

Table of Contents

Category:

History & Society

Key People:

Henri Bergson

Alasdair MacIntyre

John Austin

William Edward Hartpole Lecky

Jeremy Collier

(Show more)

Related Topics:

free will and moral responsibility

conscience

Faustian bargain

moral reasoning

duty

(Show more)

On the Web:

VIVA Open Publishing - Ethics and Society - Ethical Behavior and Moral Values in Everyday Life (Feb. 14, 2024)

(Show more)

See all related content →

morality, the moral beliefs and practices of a culture, community, or religion or a code or system of moral rules, principles, or values. The conceptual foundations and rational consistency of such standards are the subject matter of the philosophical discipline of ethics, also known as moral philosophy. In its contemporary usage, the term ethics is also applied to particular moral codes or systems and to the empirical study of their historical development and their social, economic, and geographic circumstances (see comparative ethics).(Read Peter Singer’s Britannica entry on ethics.)

More From Britannica

Christianity: Moral arguments

Empirical studies show that all societies have moral rules that prescribe or forbid certain classes of action and that these rules are accompanied by sanctions to ensure their enforcement. It has been observed, for example, that virtually every society has well-established norms dealing with matters such as family organization and individual duties, sexual activity, property rights, personal welfare, truth telling, and promise keeping. Among all societies some moral rules are nearly universal—such as those forbidding murder, theft, infidelity or adultery, and incest—while others vary between societies or exist in some societies but not in others—such as those forbidding polygamy, parricide, and feticide (abortion).

The existence of nearly universal moral rules has raised the question of whether such common practices are rooted in human nature and whether their commonality or naturalness renders them objectively valid in some sense. A related question is whether there exists a single, objectively valid moral code that is rationally discoverable even though it is not fully instantiated in the moral beliefs and practices of any society. In contrast, the diversity of moral rules between societies has raised the question of whether the validity of a moral rule is relative to the society in which it is recognized. Such questions are outside the scope of empirical studies of morality and properly within the domain of philosophical ethics. See ethical relativism. The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica This article was most recently revised and updated by Brian Duignan.

Moral Theory (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Moral Theory (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Menu

Browse

Table of Contents

What's New

Random Entry

Chronological

Archives

About

Editorial Information

About the SEP

Editorial Board

How to Cite the SEP

Special Characters

Advanced Tools

Contact

Support SEP

Support the SEP

PDFs for SEP Friends

Make a Donation

SEPIA for Libraries

Entry Navigation

Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic Tools

Friends PDF Preview

Author and Citation Info

Back to Top

Moral TheoryFirst published Mon Jun 27, 2022

There is much disagreement about what, exactly, constitutes a moral

theory. Some of that disagreement centers on the issue of

demarcating the moral from other areas of practical

normativity, such as the ethical and the aesthetic. Some

disagreement centers on the issue of what a moral

theory’s aims and functions are. In this entry,

both questions will be addressed. However, this entry is about moral

theories as theories, and is not a survey of specific

theories, though specific theories will be used as examples.

1. Morality

1.1 Common-sense Morality

1.2 Contrasts Between Morality and Other Normative Domains

2. Theory and Theoretical Virtues

2.1 The Tasks of Moral Theory

2.2 Theory Construction

3. Criteria

4. Decision Procedures and Practical Deliberation

Bibliography

Academic Tools

Other Internet Resources

Related Entries

1. Morality

When philosophers engage in moral theorizing, what is it that they are

doing? Very broadly, they are attempting to provide a systematic

account of morality. Thus, the object of moral theorizing is morality,

and, further, morality as a normative system.

At the most minimal, morality is a set of norms and principles that

govern our actions with respect to each other and which are taken to

have a special kind of weight or authority (Strawson 1961). More

fundamentally, we can also think of morality as consisting of moral

reasons, either grounded in some more basic value, or, the other way

around, grounding value (Raz 1999).

It is common, also, to hold that moral norms are universal

in the sense that they apply to and bind everyone in similar

circumstances. The principles expressing these norms are also

thought to be general, rather than specific, in that they are

formulable “without the use of what would be intuitively

recognized as proper names, or rigged definite descriptions”

(Rawls 1979, 131). They are also commonly held to be

impartial, in holding everyone to count equally.

1.1 Common-sense Morality

… Common-sense is… an exercise of the judgment unaided

by any Art or system of rules : such an exercise as we must

necessarily employ in numberless cases of daily occurrence ; in which,

having no established principles to guide us … we must needs

act on the best extemporaneous conjectures we can form. He who is

eminently skillful in doing this, is said to possess a superior degree

of Common-Sense. (Richard Whatley, Elements of Logic, 1851,

xi–xii)

“Common-Sense Morality”, as the term is used here, refers

to our pre-theoretic set of moral judgments or intuitions

or

principles.[1]

When we

engage in theory construction (see below) it is these common-sense

intuitions that provide a touchstone to theory

evaluation. Henry Sidgwick believed that the

principles of Common-Sense Morality were important in helping us

understand the “first” principle or principles

of

morality.[2]

Indeed, some theory construction explicitly appeals to puzzles in

common-sense morality that need resolution – and hence, need to

be addressed theoretically.

Features of commons sense morality are determined by our normal

reactions to cases which in turn suggest certain normative principles

or insights. For example, one feature of common-sense morality

that is often remarked upon is the self/other asymmetry in morality,

which manifests itself in a variety of ways in our intuitive

reactions. For example, many intuitively differentiate morality

from prudence in holding that morality concerns our interactions with

others, whereas prudence is concerned with the well-being of the

individual, from that individual’s point of view.

Also, according to our common-sense intuitions we are allowed to

pursue our own important projects even if such pursuit is not

“optimific” from the impartial point of view (Slote

1985). It is also considered permissible, and even admirable, for

an agent to sacrifice her own good for the sake of another even though

that is not optimific. However, it is impermissible, and outrageous,

for an agent to similarly sacrifice the well-being of another under the

same circumstances. Samuel Scheffler argued for a view in which

consequentialism is altered to include agent-centered prerogatives,

that is, prerogatives to not act so as to maximize the good (Scheffler

1982).

Our reactions to certain cases also seem to indicate a common-sense

commitment to the moral significance of the distinction between

intention and foresight, doing versus allowing, as well as the view

that distance between agent and patient is morally relevant (Kamm

2007).

Philosophers writing in empirical moral psychology have been working

to identify other features of common-sense morality, such as how prior

moral evaluations influence how we attribute moral responsibility for

actions (Alicke et. al. 2011; Knobe 2003).

What many ethicists agree upon is that common-sense is a bit of a

mess. It is fairly easy to set up inconsistencies and tensions

between common-sense commitments. The famous Trolley Problem

thought experiments illustrate how situations which are structurally

similar can elicit very different intuitions about what the morally

right course of action would be (Foot 1975). We intuitively

believe that it is worse to kill someone than to simply let the person

die. And, indeed, we believe it is wrong to kill one person to

save five others in the following scenario:

David is a great transplant surgeon. Five of his patients need new

parts—one needs a heart, the others need, respectively, liver,

stomach, spleen, and spinal cord—but all are of the same,

relatively rare, blood-type. By chance, David learns of a healthy

specimen with that very blood-type. David can take the healthy

specimen's parts, killing him, and install them in his patients, saving

them. Or he can refrain from taking the healthy specimen's parts,

letting his patients die. (Thomson 1976, 206)

And yet, in the following scenario we intuitively view it entirely

permissible, and possibly even obligatory, to kill one to save

five:

Edward is the driver of a trolley, whose brakes have just failed. On

the track ahead of him are five people; the banks are so steep that

they will not be able to get off the track in time. The track has a

spur leading off to the right, and Edward can turn the trolley onto it.

Unfortunately there is one person on the right-hand track. Edward can

turn the trolley, killing the one; or he can refrain from turning the

trolley, killing the five. (Thomson 1976, 206).

Theorizing is supposed to help resolve those tensions in a

principled way. Theory construction attempts to provide

guidance in how to resolve such tensions and how to understand

them.

1.2 Contrasts Between Morality and Other Normative Domains

1.2.1 Morality and Ethics

Ethics is generally understood to be the study of “living well

as a human being”. This is the topic of works such as

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, in which the aim of

human beings is to exemplify human excellence of character. The sense

in which we understand it here is that ethics is broader than morality,

and includes considerations of personal development of oneself and

loved ones. This personal development is important to a life well

lived, intuitively, since our very identities are centered on projects

that we find important. Bernard Williams and others refer to

these projects as “ground projects”. These are the

sources of many of our reasons for acting. For Williams, if

an agent seeks to adopt moral considerations, or be guided by

them, then important ethical considerations are neglected,

such as personal integrity and authenticity (Williams 1977; Wolf

1982). However, Williams has a very narrow view of what he

famously termed “the morality system” (Williams 1985).

Williams lists a variety of objectionable features of the morality

system, including the inescapability of moral obligations, the

overridingness of moral obligation, impartiality, and

the fact that in the morality system there is a push towards

generalization.

There has been considerable discussion of each of these features of

the morality system, and since Williams, a great deal of work on the

part of standard moral theorists on how each theory addresses the

considerations he raised. Williams’ critique of the

morality system was part of a general criticism of moral theory in the

1980s on the grounds of its uselessness, harmfulness, and even its

impossibility (Clarke 1987). This anti-theory trend was prompted

by the same dissatisfaction with consequentialism and deontology that

led to the resurgence of Virtue Ethics.

A major criticism of this view is that it has a very narrow view of

what counts as a moral theory. Thus, some of these approaches

simply rejected some features of William’s characterization of

the morality system, such as impartiality. Others, however,

Williams’ included, attacked the very project of moral

theory. This is the ‘anti-theory’ attack on moral

theorizing. For example, Annette Baier argued that

morality cannot be captured in a system of rules, and this was a very

popular theme amongst early virtue ethicists. On this view, moral

theory which systematizes and states the moral principles that ought to

guide actions is simply impossible: “Norms in the form of

virtues may be essentially imprecise in some crucial ways, may be

mutually referential, but not hierarchically orderable, may be

essentially self-referential” (Baier 220).

Robert Louden even argued that the best construal of virtue ethics

is not as an ethical theory, but as anti-theory that should not be

evaluated as attempting to theorize morality at all. (Louden

1990). According to Louden, moral theories are formulated

to a variety of reasons, including to provide solutions to problems,

formulas for action, universal principles, etc. Louden notes that this

characterization is very narrow and many would object to it, but he

views anti-theory not so much as a position against any kind

of moral theorizing, but simply the kind that he viewed as predominant

prior to the advent of Virtue Ethics. This is a much less severe

version of anti-theory as it, for example, doesn’t seem to regard

weightiness or importance of moral reasons as a problem.

Some of the problems that Williams and other anti-theorists have

posed for morality, based on the above characteristics, are:

Morality is too demanding and pervasive: that is, the view that

moral reasons are weighty indicates that we should be giving them

priority over other sorts of reasons. Further, they leach into

all aspects of our lives, leaving very little morally neutral.

Morality is alienating. There are a variety of ways in which

morality can be alienating. As Adrian Piper notes, morality might

alienate the agent from herself or might alienate the agent from others

– impartiality and universality might lead to this, for example

(Piper 1987; Stocker 1976). Another way we can understand

alienation is that the agent is alienated from the true justifications

of her own actions – this is one way to hold that theories which

opt for indirection can lead to alienation (see section 4 below).

Morality, because it is impartial, makes no room for special

obligations. That is, if the right action is the one that is impartial

between persons, then it does not favor the near and dear. On this

picture it is difficult to account for the moral requirements that

parents have towards their own children, and friends have towards each

other. These requirements are, by their nature, not

impartial.

Morality is committed to providing guides for action that can

be captured in a set of rules or general principles. That is, morality

is codifiable and the rules of morality are general.

Morality requires too much. The basic worry is that the morality

system is voracious and is creeping into all aspects of our lives, to

the detriment of other important values. The worry expressed by 4 takes

a variety of forms. For example, some take issue with a

presupposition of 4, arguing that there are no moral principles at all if we

think of these principles as guiding action. Some argue

that there are no moral principles that are complete, because morality

is not something that is codifiable. And, even if

morality was codifiable, the ‘principles’ would be

extremely specific, and not qualify as principles at all.

Since Williams’ work, philosophers have tried to respond to

the alienation worry by, for example, providing accounts of the ways in

which a person’s reasons can guide without forming an explicit

part of practical deliberation. Peter Railton, for example,

argues in favor of a form of objective consequentialism,

Sophisticated Consequentialism, in which the rightness of an

action is a function of its actual consequences (Railton 1984).

On Railton’s view, one can be a good consequentialist without

being alienated from loved ones. Though not attempting to defend moral

theory per se, other writers have also provided accounts of

how agents can act on the basis of reasons – and thus perform

morally worthy actions, even though these reasons are not explicitly

articulated in their practical deliberations (Arpaly 2002; Markovits

2014). Deontologists have argued that autonomous action needn’t

involve explicit invocation of, for example, the Categorical Imperative

(Herman 1985). Generally, what characterizes these moves is the

idea that the justifying reasons are present in some form in the

agent’s psychology – they are recoverable from the

agent’s psychology – but need not be explicitly articulated

or invoked by the agent in acting rightly.

One way to elaborate on this strategy is to argue that the morally

good agent is one who responds to the right sorts of reasons, even

though the agent can’t articulate the nature of the response

(Arpaly 2002). This strategy makes no appeal to codifiable principles,

and is compatible with a wide variety of approaches to developing a

moral theory. It relies heavily on the concept, of course, of

“reason” and “moral reason,” which many writers

on moral issues take to be fundamental or basic in any case.

There has also been debate concerning the proper scope of morality,

and how moral theories can address problems relating to

impartiality. Kant and the classical utilitarians believed that moral

reasons are impartial, what others have termed agent-neutral. Indeed,

this is one point of criticism that virtue ethics has made of these

two theories. One might argue that moral reasons are impartial, but

that there are other reasons that successfully compete with them

– reasons relating to the near and dear, for example, or

one’s own ground projects. Or, one could hold that morality

includes special reasons, arising from special obligations, that also

morally justify our actions.

The first strategy has been pursued by Bernard Williams and other

“anti-theorists”. Again, Williams argues that

morality is a special system that we would be better off without

(Williams 1985). In the morality system we see a special sense of

“obligation” – moral obligation – which

possesses certain features. For example, moral obligation is

inescapable according to the morality system. A theory

such as Kant’s, for example, holds that we must act in

accordance with the Categorical Imperative. It is not

optional. This is because morality is represented as having

authority over us in ways that even demand sacrifice of our personal

projects, of the very things that make our lives go well for us.

This seems especially clear for Utilitarianism, which holds that we

must maximize the good, and falling short of maximization is

wrong. A Kantian will try to avoid this problem by

appealing to obligations that are less demanding, the imperfect ones.

But, as Williams points out, these are still obligations, and

as such can only be overridden by other obligations. Thus, the

theories also tend to present morality as pervasive in that

morality creeps into every aspect of our lives, making no room for

neutral decisions. For example, even decisions about what shoes

to wear to work becomes a moral one:

Once the journey into more general obligations has started, we may

begin to get into trouble – not just philosophical trouble, but

the conscience trouble – with finding room for morally

indifferent actions. I have already mentioned the possible moral

conclusion that one may take some particular course of action.

That means that there is nothing else I am obliged to do. But if we have

accepted general and indeterminate obligations to further various moral

objectives…they will be waiting to provide work for idle

hands… (Williams 1985, 181)

He goes on to write that in order to get out of this problem,

“…I shall need one of those fraudulent items, a duty to

myself” (Williams 1985, 182). Kantian Ethics does supply

this. Many find this counterintuitive, since the self/other

asymmetry seems to capture the prudence/morality distinction, but

Kantians such as Tom Hill, jr. have made strong cases for at least

some moral duties to the self. In any case, for writers such

as Williams, so much the worse for morality.

Other writers, also concerned about the problems that Williams has

raised argue, instead, that morality does make room for our partial

concerns and projects, such as the norms governing our relationships,

and our meaningful projects. Virtue ethicists, for example, are

often comfortable pointing out that morality is not thoroughly

impartial because there are virtues of partiality. Being a good

mother involves having a preference for the well-being of one’s

own children. The mother who really is impartial would be a very

bad mother, lacking in the appropriate virtues.

Another option is to hold that there are partial norms, but those

partial norms are themselves justified on impartial grounds. This

can be spelled out in a variety of different ways. Consider

Marcia Baron’s defense of impartiality, where she notes that

critics of impartiality are mistaken because they confuse

levels of justification: “Critics suppose that

impartialists insisting on impartiality at the level of rules or

principles are committed to insisting on impartiality at the level of

deciding what to do in one’s day-to-day activities” (Baron

1991). This is a mistake because impartialists can justify

partial norms by appealing to impartial rules or principles. She

is correct about this. Even Jeremy Bentham believed, for example,

that the principle of utility ought not be applied in every case,

though he mainly appealed to efficiency costs of using the principle

all the time. But one can appeal to other considerations.

Frank Jackson uses an analogy with predators to argue that partial

norms are strategies for maximizing the good, they offer the best

chance of actually doing so given our limitations (Jackson 1991).

Similarly, a Kantian such as Tom Hill, jr., as Baron notes, can argue

that impartiality is part of an ideal, and ought not govern our

day-to-day lives (Hill 1987). Does this alienate people from

others? The typical mother shows the right amount of preference

for her child, let’s say, but doesn’t herself think that

this is justified on the basis of promoting the good, for

example. A friend visits another in the hospital and also does

not view the partiality as justified by any further principles.

But this is no more alienating than someone being able to make good

arguments and criticize bad ones without a knowledge of inference

rules. Maybe it is better to have an awareness of the underlying

justification, but for some theories even that is debatable. For

an objective theorist (see below) it may be that knowing the underlying

justification can interfere with doing the right thing, in which case

it is better not to know. For some theorists, however, such as

neo-Aristotelian virtue ethicists, a person is not truly virtuous

without such knowledge and understanding, though Rosalind Hursthouse

(1999) does not make this a requirement of right action.

Recently consequentialists have been approaching this issue through

the theory of value itself, arguing that there are agent-relative forms

of value. This approach is able to explain the intuitions that

support partial moral norms while retaining the general structure of

consequentialism (Sen 2000). Douglas Portmore, for example,

argues for a form of consequentialism that he terms “commonsense

consequentialism” as it is able to accommodate many of our

everyday moral intuitions (Portmore 2011). He does so by arguing

that (1) the deontic status of an act, whether it is right or wrong, is

determined by what reasons the agent has for performing it – if

an agent has a decisive reason to perform the act in question, then it

is morally required. Combined with (2) a teleological view of

practical reasons in which our reasons for performing an action are a

function of what we have reason to prefer or desire we are led to a

form of act-consequentialism but one which is open to accepting that we

have reason to prefer or desire the well-being of the near and dear

over others.

Though much of this is controversial, there is general agreement

that moral reasons are weighty, are not egoistic

– that is, to be contrasted with prudential reasons, and are

concerned with issues of value [duty, fittingness].

1.2.2. Morality and Aesthetics

Moral modes of evaluation are distinct from the aesthetic in terms

of their content, but also in terms of their authority. So, for

example, works of art are evaluated as “beautiful” or

“ugly”, and those evaluations are not generally considered

as universal or as objective as moral evaluations. These

distinctions between moral evaluation and aesthetic evaluation have

been challenged, and are the subject of some interesting debates in

metaethics on the nature of both moral and aesthetic norms and the

truth-conditions of moral and aesthetic claims. But, considered

intuitively, aesthetics seems at least less objective than

morality.

A number of writers have noted that we need to be cognizant of the

distinction between moral norms and the norms specific to other

normative areas in order to avoid fallacies of evaluation, and much

discussion has centered on a problem in aesthetics termed the

“Moralistic Fallacy” (D’Arms and Jacobson 2000).

One challenge that the anti-theorists have raised for morality was

to note that in a person’s life there will be certain norm

clashes – including clashes between types of norms such

as the moral and the aesthetic. It is giving too much prominence

to the moral that judges a person’s life as going well relative

to the fulfillment or respect of those norms. Can’t a

human life go well, even when that life sacrifices morality for

aesthetics?

This sort of debate has a long history in moral theory. For

example, it arose as a form of criticism of G. E. Moore’s Ideal

Utilitarianism, which treated beauty as an intrinsic good, and

rendering trade-offs between behaving well towards others and creating

beauty at least in principle justified morally (Moore

1903). But the anti-theorists do not pursue this method of

accommodating the aesthetic, instead arguing that it is a separate

normative realm which has its own weight and significance in human

flourishing.

2. Theory and Theoretical Virtues

There is agreement that theories play some kind

of systematizing role, and that one function is to examine

important concepts relevant to morality and moral practice and the

connections, if any, between them. For example, one very common view

in the middle of the 20th century, attributed to John

Rawls, was to view moral theory as primarily interested in

understanding the ‘right’ and the ‘good’ and

connections between the two (Rawls). Priority claims are often a

central feature in the systematizing role of moral theory. Related to

this is the issue of explanatory, or theoretical, depth. That

is, the deeper the explanation goes, the better.

Theories also strive for simplicity, coherence,

and accuracy. The fewer epicycles the theory has to postulate

the better, the parts of the theory should fit well together. For

example, the theory should not contain inconsistent principles, or have

inconsistent implications. The theory should cover the phenomena

in question. In the case of moral theories, the phenomena in

question are thought to be our considered moral intuitions or

judgements. Another coherence condition involves the theory cohering

with a person’s set of considered judgments, as well.

One last feature that needs stressing, particularly for moral

theories, is applicability. One criticism of some normative

ethical theories is that they are not applicable. For example,

Virtue Ethics has been criticized for not providing an account of what

our moral obligations are – appealing to what the

virtuous person would do in the circumstances would seem to set a very

high bar or doesn’t answer the relevant question about how we

should structure laws guiding people on what their social obligations

are. Similarly, objective consequentialists, who understand

“right action” in terms of actual consequences have been

criticized for rendering what counts as a right action in a given

circumstance unknowable, and thus useless as a guide to action.

Both approaches provide responses to this worry, but this supports the

claim that a desideratum of a moral theory is that it be

applicable.

2.1 The Tasks of Moral Theory

One task (though this is somewhat controversial) of a moral theory

is to give an account of right actions. Often, this will involve

an explication of what counts as good – some theories then get

spelled out in terms of how they approach the good, by maximizing it,

producing enough of it, honoring it, etc. In addition, some

theories explicate the right in terms of acting in accordance with

one’s duties, or acting as a virtuous person would act. In

these cases the notions of ‘duty’ and ‘virtue’

become important to the overall analysis, and one function of moral

theory is to explore the systematic connections between duty or virtue

and the right and the good.

Moral theories also have both substantive and formal aims.

Moral theories try to provide criteria for judging actions. It

might be that the criterion is simple, such as right actions maximize

the good, or it may be complex, such as the right action is the one

that gives adequate weight to each competing duty.

Sometimes, in recognition that there is not always “the”

right action, the theory simply provides an account of wrongness, or

permissibility and impermissibility, which allows that a range of

actions might count as “right”.

In addition to simply providing criteria for right or virtuous

action, or for being a virtuous person, a given moral theory, for

example, will attempt to explain why something, like an action

or character trait, has a particular moral quality, such as rightness

or virtuousness. Some theories view rightness as grounded in or

explained by value. Some view rightness as a matter of

reasons that are prior to value. In each case, to

provide an explanation of the property of ‘rightness’ or

‘virtuousness’ will be to provide an account of what the

grounding value is, or an account of reasons for action.

In addition, moral theories may also provide

decision-procedures to employ in determining how to act

rightly or virtuously, conditions on being good or virtuous, or

conditions on morally appropriate practical deliberation. Thus,

the theory provides substance to evaluation and reasons. However,

moral theories, in virtue of providing an explanatory framework, help

us see connections between criteria and decision-procedures, as well as

provide other forms of systemization. Thus, moral theories will

be themselves evaluated according to their theoretical virtues:

simplicity, explanatory power, elegance, etc. To evaluate moral

theories as theories, each needs to be evaluated in terms of

how well it succeeds in achieving these theoretical goals.

There are many more specialized elements to moral theories as

well. For example, a moral theory often concerns itself with

features of moral psychology relevant to action and character, such as

motives, intentions, emotions, and reasons responsiveness. A

moral theory that incorporates consideration of consequences into the

determination of moral quality, will also be concerned with issues

surrounding the proper aggregation of those consequences, and

the scope of the consequences to be considered.

2.2 Theory Construction

There’s been a long history of comparing moral theories to

other sorts of theories, such as scientific ones. For example, in

meta-ethics one issue has to do with the nature of moral

“evidence” on analogy with scientific evidence.

On what Ronald Dworkin terms the “natural model” the

truths of morality are discovered, just as the truths of science are

(Dworkin 1977, 160). It is our considered intuitions that provide the

clues to discover these moral truths, just as what is observable to us

provides the evidence to discover scientific truths. He compared

this model with the “constructive model” in which the

intuitions themselves are features of the theory being constructed and

are not analogous to observations of the external world.

Yet, even if we decide that morality lacks the same type of

phenomena to be accounted for as science, morality clearly figures into

our normative judgments and reactions. One might view these

– our intuitions about moral cases, for example – to

provide the basic data that needs to be accounted for by a theory on

either model.

One way to “account for” our considered intuitions would

be to debunk them. There is a long tradition of this in moral

philosophy as well. When scholars provided genealogies of

morality that explained our considered intuitions in terms of social

or evolutionary forces that are not sensitive the truth, for example,

they were debunking morality by undercutting the authority of our

intuitions to provide insight into it (Nietzsche 1887 [1998], Joyce

2001, Street 2006). In this entry, however, we consider the ways in

which moral theorists have constructed their accounts by taking the

intuitions seriously as something to be systematized, explained, and

as something that can be applied to generate the correct moral

decisions or outcomes.

Along these lines, one method used in theory construction would

involve the use of reflective equilibrium and inference to the best

explanation. For example, one might notice an apparent inconsistency

in moral judgements regarding two structurally similar cases and then

try to figure out what principle or set of principles would achieve

consistency between them. In this case, the theorist is trying to

figure out what best explains both of those intuitions. But one also

might, after thinking about principles one already accepts, or finds

plausible, reject one of those intuitions on the basis of it not

cohering with the rest of one’s considered views. But full

theory construction will go beyond this because of the fully

theoretical virtues discussed earlier. We want a systematic account

that coheres well not only with itself, but with other things that we

believe on the basis of good evidence.

3. Criteria

Consider the following:

Malory has promised to take Chris grocery shopping. Unfortunately, as

Malory is leaving the apartment, Sam calls with an urgent request:

please come over to my house right now, my pipes have broken and I

need help! Torn, Malory decides to help Sam, and thus breaks a promise

to Chris.

Has Malory done the right thing? The virtuous thing?

Malory has broken a promise, which is pro tanto wrong, but Sam

is in an emergency and needs help right away. Even if it is clear

that what Malory did was right in the circumstances, it is an

interesting question as to why it is right. What can we appeal to in

making these sorts of judgments? This brings to light the issue

of how one morally justifies one’s actions. This

is the task of understanding what the justifying reasons are for our

actions. What makes an action the thing to do in the

circumstances? This is the criterion of rightness (or

wrongness). We will focus on the criterion of rightness, though

the criterion issue comes up with other modes of moral evaluation, such

as judging an action to be virtuous, or judging it to be good in some

respect, even if not right. Indeed, some writers have argued that

‘morally right’ should be jettisoned from modern secular

ethics, as it presupposes a conceptual framework left over from

religiously based accounts which assume there is a God (Anscombe

1958). We will leave these worries aside for now, however, and

focus on standard accounts of criteria.

The following are some toy examples that exhibit differing

structural features for moral theories and set out different

criteria:

Consequentialism. The right action is the action that

produces good amongst the options open to the agent at the

time of action (Singer). The most well-known version of this

theory is Classical Utilitarianism, which holds that the right action

promotes pleasure (Mill).

Kantian Deontology. The morally worthy action is in

accordance with the Categorical Imperative, which requires an agent

refrain from acting in a way that fails to respect the rational nature

of other persons (Kant).

Rossian Deontology. The right action is the action that best

accords with the fulfillment and/or non-violation of one’s

prima facie duties (Ross).

Contractualism.An action is morally wrong if it is an act that

would be forbidden by principles that rational persons could not

reasonably reject (Scanlon).

Virtue Ethics.The right action is the action that a virtuous

person would characteristically perform in the circumstances

(Hursthouse 1999).

These principles set out the criterion or standard

for evaluation of actions. They do not necessarily tell us

how to perform right actions, and are not, in themselves,

decision-procedures, though they can easily be turned into decision

procedures, such as: you ought to try to perform the action that

maximizes the good amongst the options available to you at the time of

action. This might not be, and in ordinary circumstance probably

isn’t, a very good decision-procedure, and would itself need to

be evaluated according to the criterion set out by the theory.

These theories can be divided, roughly, into the deontological,

consequentialist, and virtue ethical categories. There has been a

lively debate about how, exactly, to delineate these categories.

Some have held that deontological theories were just those theories

that were not consequentialist. A popular conception of

consequentialist theories is that they are reductionist in a particular

way – that is, in virtue of reducing deontic features of actions

(e.g. rightness, obligatoriness) to facts about an agent’s

options and the consequences of those options (Smith 2009). If

that is the case, then it seems that deontological approaches are just

the ones that are not reductive in this manner. However, this

fails to capture the distinctive features of many forms of virtue

ethics, which are neither consequentialist nor necessarily concerned

with what we ought to do, our duties as opposed to

what sorts of persons we should be.

One way to distinguish consequentialist from deontological theories

is in terms of how each approaches value. Philip Pettit has

suggested that while consequentialist theories required

promotion of value, deontological theories recommend that

value be honored or respected. On each of

these views, value is an important component of the theory, and

theories will be partially delineated according to their theory of

value. A utilitarian such as Jeremey Bentham believes that hedonism is

the correct theory of value, whereas someone such as G. E. Moore, a

utilitarian but a pluralist regarding value, believes that hedonism is

much too narrow an account. A Kantian, on the other hand, views

value as grounded in rational nature, in a will conforming to the

Categorical Imperative.

Because of the systematizing function of moral theory discussed

earlier, the simplest account is to be preferred and thus there is a

move away from endorsing value pluralism. Of course, as intuitive

pressure is put on each of the simpler alternatives, a pluralistic

account of criteria for rightness and wrongness has the advantage of

according best with moral intuitions.

Reasons-first philosophers will delineate the theories somewhat

differently. For example, one might understand goodness as a

matter of what we have reason to desire, in which case what we have

reason to desire is prior to goodness rather than the other way

around. Value is still an important component of the theories, it

is simply that the value is grounded in reasons.

Another distinction between normative theories is that between

subjective and objective versions of a type of theory. This

distinction cuts across other categories. For example, there are

subjective forms of all the major moral theories, and objective

versions of many. An objective standard of right holds that the agent

must actually meet the standard – and meeting the standard is

something ‘objective’, not dependent on the agent’s

psychological states – in order to count as right or

virtuous. Subjective standards come in two broad forms:

Psychology sensitive: are the justifying reasons part of

the agent’s deliberative processes? Or, more weakly, are they

“recoverable” from the agent’s psychology [perhaps,

for example, the agent has a commitment to the values that provide the

reasons].

Evidence sensitive: the right action isn’t the one

that actually meets the standard, but instead, is the action that the

agent could foresee would meet that standard. [there are many

different ways to spell this out, depending on the degree of evidence

that is relevant: in terms of what the agent actually foresees, what

is foreseeable by the agent given what the agent knows, is foreseeable

by someone in possession of a reasonable amount of evidence, etc.]

Of course, these two can overlap. For theorists who are

evaluational internalists, evidence-sensitivity doesn’t

seem like a plausible way of spelling out the standard, except,

perhaps, indirectly. The distinction frequently comes up in

Consequentialism, where the Objective standard is taken to be something

like: the right action is the action that actually promotes the

good and the Subjective standard is something like: the right

action is the action that promotes the good by the agent’s own

lights (psychology sensitive) or the right action is the action that

promotes the foreseeable good, given evidence available at the time of

action (evidence sensitive standard). It is certainly possible

for other moral standards to be objective. For example, the right

action is the action that the virtuous person would perform, even

though the agent does not realize it is what the virtuous agent would

do in the circumstances, and even if the person with the best available

evidence couldn’t realize it is what the virtuous person would do

in the circumstances.

We certainly utter locutions that support both subjective and

objective uses of what we ‘ought’ to do, or what is

‘right’. Frank Jackson notes this when he writes:

…we have no alternative but to recognize a whole range of

oughts – what she ought to do by the light of her beliefs at the

time of action, …what she ought to do by the lights of one or

another onlooker who has different information on the subject, and,

what is more, what she ought to do by God’s lights…that

is, by the lights of one who knows what will and would happen

for each and every course of action. (Jackson 1991, 471).

For Jackson, the primary ought, the primary sense of

‘rightness’ for an action, is the one that is “most

immediately relevant to action” since, otherwise, we have a

problem of understanding how the action is the agent’s.

Thus, the subjective ‘ought’ is primary in the sense that

this is the one that ethical theory should be concerned with (Jackson

1991). Each type of theorist makes use of our ordinary language

intuitions to make their case. But one desideratum of a theory is that

it not simply reflect those intuitions, but also provides the tools to

critically analyze them. Given that our language allows for

both sorts of ‘ought,’ the interesting issue becomes which,

if either, has primacy in terms of actually providing the standard by

which other things are evaluated? Moral theory needn’t only

be concerned with what the right action is from the agent’s point

of view.

There are three possibilities:

neither has primacy

the subjective has primacy

the objective has primacy

First off we need to understand what we mean by

“primacy”. Again, for Frank Jackson, the primary

sense of ‘right’ or ‘ought’ is subjective,

since what we care about is the ‘right’ that refers to an

inward story, the story of our agency, so to speak. On this view,

the objective and subjective senses may have no relationship to each

other at all, and which counts as primary simply depends upon our

interests. However, the issue that concerns us here is whether or

not one sense can be accounted for in terms of the

other. Option 1 holds that there is no explanatory

connection. That is not as theoretically satisfying. Option 2

holds either there really is no meaningful objective sense, just the

subjective sense, or the objective sense is understood in terms of the

subjective.

Let’s look at the objective locution again “He did the

right thing, but he didn’t know it at the time (or he had no way

of knowing it at the time)”. Perhaps all this means is “He

did what someone with all the facts and correct set of values would

have judged right by their own lights” – this would be

extensionally the same as “He performed the action with the best

actual consequences”. This is certainly a possible account of

what objective right means which makes use of a subjective

standard. But it violates the spirit of the subjective standard, since

it ties rightness neither to the psychology of the agent, or the

evidence that is actually available to the agent. For that reason, it

seems more natural to opt for 3. An advantage of this option is that

gives us a nice, unified account regarding the connection between the

objective and the subjective. Subjective standards, then, are

standards of praise and blame, which are themselves evaluable

according to the objective standard. Over time, people are in a

position to tell whether or not a standard actually works in a given

type of context. Or, perhaps it turns out that there are several

standards of blame that differ in terms of severity. For example,

if someone acts negligently a sensible case can be made that the person

is blameworthy but not as blameworthy as if they had acted

intentionally.

As to the worry that the objective standard doesn’t provide

action guidance, the objective theorist can hold that action guidance

is provided by the subjective standards of

praise/blameworthiness. Further, the standard itself can provide

what we need for action guidance through normative review (Driver

2012). Normative review is a retrospective look at what does in fact

meet the standard, and under what circumstances.

Now, consider a virtue ethical example. The right action is

the action that is the actual action that a virtuous person would

perform characteristically, in the circumstances, rather than the

action that the agent believes is the one the virtuous person would

perform. Then we evaluate an agent’s “v-rules”

in terms of how close they meet the virtuous ideal.

4. Decision Procedures and Practical Deliberation

Another function of moral theory is to provide a decision procedure

for people to follow so as to best insure they perform right

actions. Indeed, some writers, such as R. M. Hare hold action guidance

to be the function of the moral principles of the theory (Hare

1965). This raises the question of what considerations are relevant to

the content of such principles – for example, should the

principles be formulated taking into account the epistemic limitations

of most human beings? The requirement that moral principles be action

guiding is what Holly Smith terms the “Useability Demand”:

“…an acceptable moral principle must be useable for

guiding moral decisions…” (Smith 2020, 11). Smith

enumerates different forms satisfaction of this demand can take, and

notes that how one spells out a principle in order to meet the demand

will depend upon how the moral theorist views moral success. For

example, whether or not success is achieved in virtue of simply making

the right decision or if, in addition to making the right decision,

the agent must also have successful follow-through on that

decision.

There has been enormous debate on the issue of what is involved in

following a rule or principle, and some skepticism that this is in fact

what we are doing when we take ourselves to be following a

rule. (Kripke 1982) Some virtue theorists believe that it is moral

perception that actually does the guiding, and that a virtuous person

is able to perceive what is morally relevant and act accordingly

(McDowell 1979).

As discussed earlier in the section on criteria, however, this is

also controversial in that some theorists believe that decision

procedures themselves are not of fundamental significance. Again,

objective consequentialist who believes that the fundamental task of

theory is to establish a criterion for right argues that decision

procedures will themselves be established and evaluated on the basis of

how well they get us to actually achieving the right. Thus, the

decision-procedures are derivative. Others, such as subjective

consequentialists, will argue that the decision-procedures

specify the criterion in the sense that following the

decision-procedure itself is sufficient for meeting the

criterion. For example, an objective consequentialist will hold

that the right action maximizes the good, whereas the subjective

consequentialist might hold that the right action is to try to

maximize the good, whether or not one actually achieves it (Mason 2003

and 2019). Following the decision-procedure itself,

then, is the criterion.

The distinction between criterion and decision-procedure has been

acknowledged and discussed at least since Sidgwick, though it was also

mentioned by earlier ethicists. This distinction allows ethical

theories to avoid wildly implausible implications. For example,

if the standard that the theory recommends is ‘promote the

good’ it would be a mistake to think that ‘promote the

good’ needs to be part of the agent’s

deliberation. The consequentialist might say that, instead, it is

an empirical issue as to what the theory is going to recommend as a

decision-procedure, and that recommendation could vary from context to

context. There will surely be circumstances in which it would be

best to think in terms of meeting the standard itself, but again that

is an empirical issue. Likewise, it is open to a Virtue Ethicist

to hold that the right action is the one the virtuous agent would

perform in the circumstances, but also hold that the agent’s

deliberative processes need not make reference to the standard.

Pretty much all theories will want to make some space between the

standard and the decision-procedure in order to avoid a requirement

that agent’s must think in terms of the correct standard, in

order to act rightly, or even act with moral worth. There is a

distinction to be made between doing the right thing, and doing the

right thing for the right reasons. Doing the right thing for

the right reasons makes the action a morally worthy one, as it exhibits

a good quality of the will. It is possible for a theory to hold

that the ‘good will’ is one that understands the underlying

justification of an action, but that seems overly demanding. If

consequentialism is the correct theory, then demanding that people must

explicitly act intentionally to maximize the good would result in fewer

morally worthy actions than seems plausible. The ‘for the

right reasons’ must be understood as allowing for no explicit

invocation of the true justifying standard.

This has led to the development of theories that advocate

indirection. First, we need to distinguish two ways that

indirection figures into moral philosophy.

Indirection in evaluation of right action.

Indirection in that the theory does not necessarily advocate the

necessity of aiming for the right action.

To use Utilitarianism as an example again, Rule Utilitarianism is an

example of the first sort of indirection (Hooker 2000),

Sophisticated Consequentialism is an example of the second

sort of indirection (Railton 1984). One might hold that some

versions of Aristotelian Virtue ethics, such as Rosalind

Hursthouse’s version, also are of the first type, since

right action is understood in terms of virtue. One could imagine

an indirect consequentialist view with a similar structure: the

right action is the action that the virtuous person would perform,

where virtue is understood as a trait conducive to the good, instead of

by appeal to an Aristotelian notion of human flourishing.

The second sort relies on the standard/decision-procedure

distinction. Railton argues that personal relationships are good

for people, and explicitly trying to maximize the good is not a part of

our relationship norms, so it is likely good that we develop

dispositions to focus on and pay special attention to our loved

ones. The account is open to the possibility that people who

don’t believe in consequentialism have another way of deciding

how to act that is correlated with promotion of the good. If the

criteria a theory sets out need not be fulfilled by the agent guiding

herself with the reasons set out by the criteria, then it is termed

self-effacing. When a theory is self-effacing, it has

the problem of alienating a person from the justification of her own

actions. A middle ground, which is closer to Railton’s

view, holds that the correct justification is a kind of

“touchstone” to the morally good person – consulted

periodically for self-regulation, but not taken explicitly into

consideration in our ordinary, day-to-day lives. In this way, the

theory would not be utterly self-effacing and the agent would still

understand the moral basis for her own actions.

Bibliography

Alicke, Mark, David Rose and Dori Bloom, 2011, “Causation,

Norm Violation, and Culpable Control,” Journal of

Philosophy, 108(12): 670–696.

Annas, Julia, 2011, Intelligent Virtue, New York: Oxford

University Press.

Arpaly, Nomy, 2002, Unprincipled Virtue, New York: Oxford

University Press.

Baier, Annette, 1985, Postures of the Mind, Minneapolis,

MN: University of Minnesota Press.

Baron, Marcia, 1991, “Impartiality and Friendship,”

Ethics, 101(4): 836–857.

–––, 1995, Kantian Ethics Almost Without

Apology, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Clarke, Stanley G, 1987, “Anti-Theory in Ethics,”

American Philosophical Quarterly, 24(3): 237–244.

D’Arms, Justin and Daniel Jacobson, 2000 , “The

Moralistic Fallacy: On the ‘Appropriateness’ of

Emotions,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,

61(1): 65–90.

Darwall, Stephen, 2006, The Second-Person Standpoint,

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Dreier, Jamie, 1993, “Structures of Normative Theories,”

The Monist, 76(1): 22–40.

Driver, Julia, 2012, “What the Objective Standard is Good

For,” in Mark Timmons (ed.), Oxford Studies in

Normative Ethics, New York: Oxford University Press, 28–44.

Dworkin, Ronald, 1977, Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge,

MA: Harvard University Press.

Foot, Philippa, 1967, “Abortion and the Doctrine of Double

Effect,” Oxford Review, 5: 5–15.

Graham, Peter, 2010, “In Defense of Objectivism About Moral

Obligation,” Ethics, 121(1): 88–115.

Hare, R. M., 1965, Freedom and Reason, New York: Oxford

University Press.

Herman, Barbara, 1985, “The Practice of Moral Judgment,”

Journal of Philosophy, 82(8): 414–436.

Hill, jr., Thomas E., 1987, “The Importance of

Autonomy,” in Eva Kittay and Diana Meyers (ed.) Women and

Moral Theory, Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld,

129–138.

Hooker, Brad, 2000, Ideal Code, Real World, New York:

Oxford University Press.

Hurka, Thomas, 2001, Virtue, Vice, and Value, New

York: Oxford University Press.

Hursthouse, Rosalind, 1999, On Virtue Ethics, New York:

Oxford University Press.

Jackson, Frank, 1991, “Decision-theoretic

Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection,”

Ethics, 101(3): 461–482.

Jeske, Diane, 2008, Rationality and Moral Theory: How Intimacy

Generates Reasons, New York: Routledge.

Joyce, Richard, 2001, The Myth of Morality, New York:

Cambridge University Press.

Keas, Michael, 2018, “Systematizing the Theoretical

Virtues,” Synthese, 195: 2761–2793.

Kagan, Shelley, 1989, The Limits of Morality, New York:

Oxford University Press.

Kamm, Frances, 2007, Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities,

and Permissible Harm, New York: Oxford University Press.

Kant, Immanuel, 1785 [2012], Groundwork of the Metaphysics of

Morals, tr. by Mary Gregor and Jens Timmerman, New York:

Cambridge University Press, 2012.

Knobe, Joshua, 2003, “Intentional Action in Folk Psychology:

An Experimental Investigation,” Philosophical

Psychology, 16(2): 309–325.

Kripke, Saul, 1982, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private

Languages, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Louden, Robert, 1990, “Virtue Ethics and Anti-Theory,”

Philosophia, 20(1–2): 93–114.

Markovits, Julia, 2014, Moral Reason, New York: Oxford

University Press.

Mason, Elinor, 2003, “Consequentialism and the ‘Ought

Implies Can’ Principle,” American Philosophical

Quarterly, 40(4): 319–331.

–––, 2019, Ways to Be Blameworthy:

Rightness, Wrongness, and Responsibility, New York: Oxford

University Press.

McDowell, John, 1979, “Virtue and Reason,” The

Monist, 62(3): 331–350.

Moody-Adams, Michelle, 2002, Fieldwork in Familiar Places:

Morality, Culture, and Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

Moore, G. E., 1903 [1993], Principia Ethica, ed. Thomas

Baldwin, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993.

Nagel, Thomas, 1979, “The Fragmentation of Value,” in

Mortal Questions, New York: Cambridge University Press,

128–141.

Nietzsche, Friedrich, 1887 [1998], On the Genealogy of

Morality, Maudemarie Clark and Alan J. Swensen (trans.),

Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.

Norcross, Alastair, 2020, Morality By Degrees, New

York: Oxford University Press.

Olson, Jonas, 2004, “Buck-Passing and the Wrong Kind of

Reasons,” Philosophical Quarterly, 54(215): 295–300.

Parfit, Derek, 1984, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon

Press.

Pettit, Phillip, 1997, “The Consequentialist

Perspective,” in The Three Methods of Ethics, by Marcia

Baron, Phillip Pettit, and Michael Slote, Oxford: Blackwell,

92–174.

Pettit, Phillip, and Michael Smith, 2000, “Global

Consequentialism,” in Brad Hooker, et al. (eds.), Morality,

Rules, and Consequences, Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh

Press, 121–133.

Phillips, David, 2019, Rossian Ethics, New York: Oxford

University Press.

Piper, Adrian, 1987, “Moral Theory and Moral

Alienation,” Journal of Philosophy, 82(2): 102–118.

Portmore, Douglas, 2011, Commonsense Consequentialism, New

York: Oxford University Press.

Rabinowicz, Wlodek and Toni Ronnow-Rasmussen, 2004, “The

Strike of the Demon: on Fitting Pro-Attitudes and Value,”

Ethics, 114(3): 391–423.

Railton, Peter, 1984, “Alienation, Consequentialism, and

the Demands of Morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs,

13(2): 134–171.

Rawls, John, 1971, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA:

Belknap Press.

Scanlon, T. M., 1998, What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge,

MA: Belknap Press.

–––, 2008, Moral Dimensions, Cambridge,

MA: Harvard University Press.

Scheffler, Samuel, 1982, The Rejection of Consequentialism,

New York: Oxford University Press.

Schneewind, J. B., 1963, “First Principles and Common-sense

Morality in Sidgwick’s Ethics,” Archiv fur Geschichte

der Philosophie, 45(2): 137–156.

–––, 1990, “The Misfortunes of

Virtue,” Ethics, 101(1): 42–63.

Schofield, Paul, 2021, Duty to Self: Moral, Political, and Legal

Self-Relation, New York: Oxford University Press.

Sen, Amartya, 2000, “Consequential Evaluation and Practical

Reason,” The Journal of Philosophy, 47(9): 477–502.

Sidgwick, Henry, 1874 [1907], The Methods of Ethics,

London: Macmillan. [The seventh edition was published in 1907.]

Singer, Marcus, 1986, “Ethics and Common Sense,”

Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 40(158): 221–258.

Slote, Michael, 1985, Common-Sense Morality and

Consequentialism, New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

–––, 2007, The Ethics of Care and

Empathy, New York: Routledge.

Smith, Holly, 2018, Making Morality Work, New York:

Oxford University Press.

Smith, Michael, 2009, “Two Kinds of Consequentialism,”

Philosophical Issues, 19(1): 257–272.

Stark, Cynthia, 1997, “Decision Procedures, Standards of

Rightness and Impartiality,” Noûs, 31(4): 478–495.

Stocker, Michael, 1976, “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical

Theories,” Journal of Philosophy, 73(14): 453–466.

Strawson, Peter, 1961, “Social Morality and Individual

Ideal,” Philosophy, 36(136): 1–17.

Street, Sharon, 2006, “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist

Theories of Value,” Philosophical Studies, 127(1):

109–166.

Thomson, Judith Jarvis, 1976, “Killing, Letting Die, and the

Trolley Problem,” The Monist, 59(2): 204–217.

Wiland, Eric J, “The Incoherence Objection in Moral

Theory,” Acta Analytica, 25(3): 279–284.

Williams, Bernard, 1985, Ethics and the Limits of

Philosophy, New York: Oxford University Press.

Wolf, Susan, 1982, “Moral Saints,” Journal of

Philosophy, 79(8): 419–439.

–––, 2014, “Loving Attention: Lessons in

Love from The Philadelphia Story,” in Susan Wolf and

Christopher Grau (eds.), Understanding Love: Philosophy, Film, and

Fiction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 369–386.

Zagzebski, Linda Trinkhaus, 2017, Exemplarist Moral Theory,

New York: Oxford University Press.

Academic Tools

How to cite this entry.

Preview the PDF version of this entry at the

Friends of the SEP Society.

Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry

at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).

Enhanced bibliography for this entry

at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Related Entries

consequentialism |

ethics: deontological |

ethics: virtue |

morality, definition of |

value theory

Copyright © 2022 by

Julia Driver

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.

The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support

Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

Browse

Table of Contents

What's New

Random Entry

Chronological

Archives

About

Editorial Information

About the SEP

Editorial Board

How to Cite the SEP

Special Characters

Advanced Tools

Accessibility

Contact

Support SEP

Support the SEP

PDFs for SEP Friends

Make a Donation

SEPIA for Libraries

Mirror Sites

View this site from another server:

USA (Main Site)

Philosophy, Stanford University

Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

The Definition of Morality (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

The Definition of Morality (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Menu

Browse

Table of Contents

What's New

Random Entry

Chronological

Archives

About

Editorial Information

About the SEP

Editorial Board

How to Cite the SEP

Special Characters

Advanced Tools

Contact

Support SEP

Support the SEP

PDFs for SEP Friends

Make a Donation

SEPIA for Libraries

Entry Navigation

Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic Tools

Friends PDF Preview

Author and Citation Info

Back to Top

The Definition of MoralityFirst published Wed Apr 17, 2002; substantive revision Tue Sep 8, 2020

The topic of this entry is not—at least directly—moral

theory; rather, it is the definition of morality. Moral

theories are large and complex things; definitions are not. The

question of the definition of morality is the question of identifying

the target of moral theorizing. Identifying this target

enables us to see different moral theories as attempting to capture

the very same thing. And it enables psychologists, anthropologists,

evolutionary biologists, and other more empirically-oriented theorists

to design their experiments or formulate their hypotheses without

prejudicing matters too much in terms of the specific content a code,

judgment, or norm must have in order to count as distinctively

moral.

There does not seem to be much reason to think that a single

definition of morality will be applicable to all moral discussions.

One reason for this is that “morality” seems to be used in

two distinct broad senses: a descriptive sense and a normative sense.

More particularly, the term “morality” can be used

either

descriptively to refer to certain codes of conduct put forward by

a society or a group (such as a religion), or accepted by an

individual for her own behavior, or

normatively to refer to a code of conduct that, given specified

conditions, would be put forward by all rational people.

Which of these two senses of “morality” a moral

philosopher is using plays a crucial, although sometimes

unacknowledged, role in the development of an ethical theory. If one

uses “morality” in its descriptive sense, and therefore

uses it to refer to codes of conduct actually put forward by distinct

groups or societies, one will almost certainly deny that there is a

universal morality that applies to all human beings. The descriptive

use of “morality” is the one used by anthropologists when

they report on the morality of the societies that they study.

Recently, some comparative and evolutionary psychologists (Haidt 2006;

Hauser 2006; De Waal 1996) have taken morality, or a close

anticipation of it, to be present among groups of non-human animals:

primarily, but not exclusively, other primates.

Accepting that there are two uses or senses of

“morality”—a descriptive sense and a normative

sense—does not commit one to holding that the “distinction

between descriptions and norms—between what is and what ought to

be—is obvious and unbridgeable”, as some have held that it

does (Churchland 2011: 185). To see this, note that it is obvious that

there is a descriptive sense of morality. That is, it is obvious that

one can sensibly describe the moralities of various groups without

making any normative claims. And it should be equally obvious that

that one might hold that a certain code of conduct would be put

forward by all rational people under certain conditions without having

any particular views about the nature of the is/ought gap or the

possibility of crossing it.

Any definition of “morality” in the descriptive sense will

need to specify which of the codes put forward by a society

or group count as moral. Even in small homogeneous societies that have

no written language, distinctions are sometimes made between morality,

etiquette, law, and religion. And in larger and more complex societies

these distinctions are often sharply marked. So “morality”

cannot be taken to refer to every code of conduct put forward by a

society.

In the normative sense, “morality” refers to a code of

conduct that would be accepted by anyone who meets certain

intellectual and volitional conditions, almost always including the

condition of being rational. That a person meets these conditions is

typically expressed by saying that the person counts as a moral

agent. However, merely showing that a certain code would be

accepted by any moral agent is not enough to show that the code is the

moral code. It might well be that all moral agents would also accept a

code of prudence or rationality, but this would not by itself show

that prudence was part of morality. So something else must be added;

for example, that the code can be understood to involve a certain kind

of impartiality, or that it can be understood as having the function

of making it possible for people to live together in groups.

As we’ve just seen, not all codes that are put forward by

societies or groups are moral codes in the descriptive sense of

morality, and not all codes that would be accepted by all moral

agents are moral codes in the normative sense of morality. So any

definition of morality—in either sense—will require

further criteria. Still, each of these two very brief descriptions of

codes might be regarded as offering some features of morality that

would be included in any adequate definition. In that way they might

be taken to be offering some definitional features of

morality, in each of its two senses. When one has specified enough

definitional features to allow one to classify all the relevant moral

theories as theories of a common subject, one might then be taken to

have given a definition of morality. This is the sense of

“definition” at work in this entry.

Explicit attempts, by philosophers, to define morality are hard to

find, at least since the beginning of the twentieth century. One

possible explanation for this is the combined effect of early

positivistic worries about the metaphysical status of normative

properties, followed (or augmented) by Wittgensteinian worries about

definitions of any significant terms whatsoever. Whatever the

explanation, when definitions have been offered, they have tended to

be directed at the notion of moral judgment (Hare 1952, 1981) rather

than at morality itself. However, to the degree that these definitions

of moral judgment are adequate, they might, without much effort, be

converted into definitions of morality in the descriptive sense. For

example, a particular person’s morality might be regarded as the

content of the basic moral judgments that person is prepared to

accept.

One might use a detailed definition of moral judgment to define

morality in a descriptive sense in another way—other than simply

as the content of a person’s moral judgments, or the content of

the moral judgments that prevail in a certain society or group. In

particular, the very features of a judgment that make it qualify as a

moral judgment might be transposed from a psychological key to

something more abstract. Here is one simplified example. Suppose that

a negative judgment of an action only counts as a negative moral

judgment if it involves the idea that there is a prima facie case for

punishing that action. In that case, a definition of morality in the

descriptive sense will include a corresponding idea: that the

prohibitions of morality, taken in the descriptive sense, are those

that are backed by the threat of punishment. Of course, if one goes

this route, other conditions will need to be included, to

differentiate morality from criminal law.

What counts as definitional of morality, in either sense of

“morality”, is controversial. Moreover, the line between

what is part of a definition, in the sense at issue, and what is part

of a moral theory, is not entirely sharp. For example, some might

regard it as definitional of morality, in the normative sense, that it

governs only interpersonal interactions. Others, however, might take

this to be a substantive theoretical claim. Some might take it as

definitional of “morality” in its descriptive sense that

it be a code of conduct that a person or group takes to be most

important. But others might say that attention to religion casts doubt

on this idea.

“Morality”, when used in a descriptive sense, has an

important feature that “morality” in the normative sense

does not have: a feature that stems from its relational nature. This

feature is the following: that if one is not a member of the relevant

society or group, or is not the relevant individual, then accepting a

certain account of the content of a morality, in the descriptive

sense, has no implications for how one thinks one should behave. On

the other hand, if one accepts a moral theory’s account of moral

agents, and of the conditions under which all moral agents would

endorse a code of conduct as a moral code, then one accepts that moral

theory’s normative definition of “morality”.

Accepting an account of “morality” in the normative sense

commits one to regarding some behavior as immoral, perhaps even

behavior that one is tempted to perform. Because accepting an account

of “morality” in the normative sense involves this

commitment, it is not surprising that philosophers seriously disagree

about which account to accept.

1. Is Morality Unified Enough to Define?

2. Descriptive Definitions of “Morality”

3. Implicit and Explicit Definitions in Allied Fields

4. Normative Definitions of “Morality”

5. Variations

5.1 Morality as linked to norms for responses to behavior

5.2 Morality as linked to advocacy of a code

5.3 Morality as linked to acceptance of a code

5.4 Morality as linked to justification to others

Bibliography

Academic Tools

Other Internet Resources

Related Entries

1. Is Morality Unified Enough to Define?

An assumption suggested by the very existence of this encyclopedia

entry is that there is some unifying set of features in virtue of

which all moral systems count as moral systems. But Sinnott-Armstrong

(2016) directly argues against an analogous hypothesis in connection

with moral judgments, and also seems to take this view to suggest that

morality itself is not a unified domain. He points out that moral

judgments cannot be unified by any appeal to the notion of harm to

others, since there are such things as moral ideals, and there are

harmless behaviors that a significant number of people regard as

morally wrong: Sinnott-Armstrong gives example such as cannibalism and

flag-burning. Whether people who condemn such behaviors morally are

correct in those judgments is largely irrelevant to the question of

whether they count as moral in the first place.

Sinnott-Armstrong seems right in holding that moral judgments cannot

be delimited from other judgments simply by appeal to their content.

It seems quite possible for someone to have been raised in such a way

as to hold that it is morally wrong for adult men to wear shorts. And

it also seems plausible that, as he also argues, moral judgments

cannot be identified by reference to any sort of neurological feature

common and peculiar to them and them alone. A third strategy might be

to claim that moral judgments are those one makes as a result of

having been inducted into a social practice that has a certain

function. However, this function cannot simply be to help facilitate

the sorts of social interactions that enable societies to flourish and

persist, since too many obviously non-moral judgments do this.

Beyond the problem just described, attempts to pick out moral codes in

the descriptive sense by appeal to their function often seem to be

specifying the function that the theorist thinks morality, in the

normative sense, would serve, rather than the function that actual

moralities do serve. For example, Greene claims that

morality is a set of psychological adaptations that allow otherwise

selfish individuals to reap the benefits of cooperation, (2013: 23)

and Haidt claims that

moral systems are interlocking sets of values, virtues, norms,

practices, identities, institutions, technologies, and evolved

psychological mechanisms that work together to suppress or regulate

self-interest and make cooperative societies possible. (2011: 270)

But these claims need to deal with the existence of dysfunctional

moralities that do not in fact serve these functions. Perhaps this

problem could be alleviated by pointing out that many instances of a

kind that have a function—for example, an actual human

heart—fail to fulfill that function.

Even if Sinnott-Armstrong’s position is correct with regard to

morality in the descriptive sense, there might nevertheless be a code

of conduct that, given certain specified conditions, would be put

forward by all rational agents. That is, even if the descriptive sense

of morality is a family-resemblance notion, vaguely bordered and

open-textured, or even if it is significantly disjunctive and

disunified, the normative sense might not be. By way of comparison, we

might think of the notion of food in two ways: as what people regard

as food, and as what they would regard as food if they were rational and

fully informed. Certainly there is not much that unifies the first

category: not even being digestible or nutritious, since people regard

various indigestible and non-nutritious substances as food, and forego

much that is digestible and nutritious. But that does not mean that we

cannot theorize about what it would be rational to regard as food.

2. Descriptive Definitions of “Morality”

An initial naïve attempt at a descriptive definition of

“morality” might take it to refer to the most important

code of conduct put forward by a society and accepted by the members

of that society. But the existence of large and heterogeneous

societies raises conceptual problems for such a descriptive

definition, since there may not be any such society-wide code that is

regarded as most important. As a result, a definition might be offered

in which “morality” refers to the most important code of

conduct put forward and accepted by any group, or even by an

individual. Apart from containing some prohibitions on harming

(certain) others, different moralities—when

“morality” is understood in this way—can vary in

content quite substantially.

Etiquette is sometimes included as a part of morality, applying to

norms that are considered less serious than the kinds of norms for

behavior that are more central to morality. Hobbes expresses this sort

of view when he uses the term “small morals” to describe

“decency of behavior, as how one man should salute another, or

how a man should wash his mouth or pick his teeth before

company”, and distinguishes these from “those qualities of

mankind that concern their living together in peace and unity”

(1660 [1994]: Chapter XI, paragraph 1). When etiquette is included as

part of morality, morality is almost always being understood in the

descriptive sense. One reason for this is that it is clear that the

rules of etiquette are relative to a society or group. Moreover, there

are no plausible conditions under which we could pick out the

“correct” rules of etiquette as those that would be

accepted by all rational beings.

Law is distinguished from morality by having explicit written rules,

penalties, and officials who interpret the laws and apply the

penalties. Although there is often considerable overlap in the conduct

governed by morality and that governed by law, laws are often

evaluated—and changed—on moral grounds. Some theorists,

including Ronald Dworkin (1986), have even maintained that the

interpretation of law must make use of morality.

Although the morality of a group or society may derive from its

religion, morality and religion are not the same thing, even in that

case. Morality is only a guide to conduct, whereas religion is always

more than this. For example, religion includes stories about events in

the past, usually about supernatural beings, that are used to explain

or justify the behavior that it prohibits or requires. Although there

is often a considerable overlap in the conduct prohibited or required

by religion and that prohibited or required by morality, religions may

prohibit or require more than is prohibited or required by guides to

behavior that are explicitly labeled as moral guides, and may

recommend some behavior that is prohibited by morality. Even when

morality is not regarded as the code of conduct that is put forward by

a formal religion, it is often thought to require some religious

explanation and justification. However, just as with law, some

religious practices and precepts are criticized on moral grounds,

e.g., that the practice or precept involves discrimination on the

basis of race, gender, or sexual orientation.

When “morality” is used simply to refer to a code of

conduct put forward by an actual group, including a society, even if

it is distinguished from etiquette, law, and religion, it is being

used in a descriptive sense. It is also being used in the descriptive

sense when it refers to important attitudes of individuals. Just as

one can refer to the morality of the Greeks, so one can refer to the

morality of a particular person. This descriptive use of

“morality” is now becoming more prominent because of the

work of psychologists such as Jonathan Haidt (2006), who have been

influenced by the views of David Hume (1751), including his attempt to

present a naturalistic account of moral judgments.

Guides to behavior that are regarded as moralities normally involve

avoiding and preventing harm to others (Frankena 1980), and perhaps

some norm of honesty (Strawson 1961). But all of them involve other

matters as well, and Hare’s view of morality as that which is

most important allows that these other matters may be more important

than avoiding and preventing harm to others (Hare 1952, 1963, 1981).

This view of morality as concerning that which is most important to a

person or group allows matters related to religious practices and

precepts, or matters related to customs and traditions, e.g., purity

and sanctity, to be more important than avoiding and preventing

harm.

When “morality” is used in a descriptive sense, moralities

can differ from each other quite extensively in their content and in

the foundation that members of the society claim their morality to

have. Some societies may claim that their morality, which is more

concerned with purity and sanctity, is based on the commands of God.

The descriptive sense of “morality”, which allows for the

view that morality is based on religion in this way, picks out codes

of conduct that are often in significant conflict with all normative

accounts of morality.

A society might have a morality that takes accepting its traditions

and customs, including accepting the authority of certain people and

emphasizing loyalty to the group, as more important than avoiding and

preventing harm. Such a morality might not count as immoral any

behavior that shows loyalty to the preferred group, even if that

behavior causes significant harm to innocent people who are not in

that group. The familiarity of this kind of morality, which makes

in-group loyalty almost equivalent to morality, seems to allow some

comparative and evolutionary psychologists, including Frans De Waal

(1996), to regard non-human animals to be acting in ways very similar

to those that are regarded as moral.

Although all societies include more than just a concern for minimizing

harm to (some) human beings in their moralities, this feature of

morality, unlike purity and sanctity, or accepting authority and

emphasizing loyalty, is included in everything that is regarded as a

morality by any society. Because minimizing harm can conflict with

accepting authority and emphasizing loyalty, there can be fundamental

disagreements within a society about the morally right way to behave

in particular kinds of situations. Philosophers such as Bentham (1789)

and Mill (1861), who accept a normative account of morality that takes

the avoiding and preventing harm element of morality to be most

important, criticize all actual moralities (referred to by

“morality” in the descriptive sense) that give precedence

to purity and loyalty when they are in conflict with avoiding and

preventing harm.

Some psychologists, such as Haidt, take morality to include concern

with, at least, all three of the triad of (1) harm, (2) purity, and

(3) loyalty, and hold that different members of a society can and do

take different features of morality to be most important. But beyond a

concern with avoiding and preventing such harms to members of certain

groups, there may be no common content shared by all moralities in the

descriptive sense. Nor may there be any common justification that

those who accept morality claim for it; some may appeal to religion,

others to tradition, and others to rational human nature. Beyond the

concern with harm, the only other feature that all descriptive

moralities have in common is that they are put forward by an

individual or a group, usually a society, in which case they provide a

guide for the behavior of the people in that group or society. In the

descriptive sense of “morality”, morality may not even

incorporate impartiality with regard to all moral agents, and it may

not be universalizable in any significant way (compare MacIntyre

1957).

Although most philosophers do not use “morality” in any of

the above descriptive senses, some philosophers do. Ethical

relativists such as Harman (1975), Westermarck (1960), and Prinz

(2007), deny that there is any universal normative morality and claim

that the actual moralities of societies or individuals are the only

moralities there are. These relativists hold that only when the term

“morality” is used in this descriptive sense is there

something that “morality” actually refers to. They claim

that it is a mistake to take “morality” to refer to a

universal code of conduct that, under certain conditions, would be

endorsed by all rational persons. Although ethical relativists admit

that many speakers of English use “morality” to refer to

such a universal code of conduct, they claim such persons are mistaken

in thinking that there is anything that is the referent of the word

“morality” taken in that sense.

Wong (1984, 2006, 2014) claims to be an ethical relativist because he

denies that there is any universal moral code that would be endorsed

by all rational people. But what seems to stand behind this claim is

the idea that there are cultural variations in the relative weights

given to, for example, considerations of justice and considerations of

interpersonal responsibility. And he assumes that those who believe in

a universal morality are committed to the idea that “if there is

fundamental disagreement, someone has got it wrong” (2014: 339).

But Gert (2005) is certainly not a relativist, and it is central to

his moral theory that there are fundamental disagreements in the

rankings of various harms and benefits, and with regard to who is

protected by morality, and no unique right answer in such cases. Wong

himself is willing to say that some moralities are better than others,

because he thinks that the moral domain is delimited by a functional

criterion: among the functions of a morality are that it promote and

regulate social cooperation, help individuals rank their own

motivations, and reduce harm.

When used with its descriptive sense, “morality” can refer

to codes of conduct with widely differing content, and still be used

unambiguously. This parallels the way in which “law” is

used unambiguously even though different societies have laws with

widely differing content. However, when “morality” is used

in its descriptive sense, it sometimes does not refer to the code of a

society, but to the code of a group or an individual. As a result,

when the guide to conduct put forward by, for example, a religious

group conflicts with the guide to conduct put forward by a society, it

is not clear whether to say that there are conflicting moralities,

conflicting elements within morality, or that the code of the

religious group conflicts with morality.

In small homogeneous societies there may be a guide to behavior that

is put forward by the society and that is accepted by (almost) all

members of the society. For such societies there is (almost) no

ambiguity about which guide “morality” refers to. However,

in larger societies people often belong to groups that put forward

guides to behavior that conflict with the guide put forward by their

society, and members of the society do not always accept the guide put

forward by their society. If they accept the conflicting guide of some

other group to which they belong (often a religious group) rather than

the guide put forward by their society, in cases of conflict they will

regard those who follow the guide put forward by their society as

acting immorally.

In the descriptive sense of “morality”, a person’s

own morality cannot be a guide to behavior that that person would

prefer others not to follow. However, that fact that an individual

adopts a moral code of conduct for his own use does not entail that

the person requires it to be adopted by anyone else. An

individual may adopt for himself a very demanding moral guide that he

thinks may be too difficult for most others to follow. He may judge

people who do not adopt his code of conduct as not being as morally

good as he is, without judging them to be immoral if they do not adopt

it. However, such cases do not undermine the restriction; a guide is

plausibly referred to as a morality only when the individual would be

willing for others to follow it, at least if

“follow” is taken to mean “successfully

follow”. For it may be that the individual would not be willing

for others to try to follow that code, because of worries

about the bad effects of predictable failures due to partiality or

lack of sufficient foresight or intelligence.

3. Implicit and Explicit Definitions in Allied Fields

Philosophers, because they do not need to produce operational tests or

criteria in the way that psychologists, biologists, and

anthropologists do, often simply take for granted that everyone knows

what belongs, and does not belong, to the moral domain. This attitude

finds expression in the philosopher’s common appeal to

intuition, or to what everyone agrees about. For example, Michael

Smith (1994) provides a very detailed analysis of normative reasons,

but in distinguishing specifically moral reasons from other sorts of

reasons, he says only that they are picked out by appeal to a number

of platitudes. And he makes no effort to provide anything like a

comprehensive list of such platitudes. Moreover, it is very likely

that there will be disagreement as to what counts as

platitudinous. Or, if it is definitional of “platitude”

that it be uncontroversial, it may be that what is platitudinous about

morality will be so thin as to fail to separate morality from other

domains. Failing to specify which particular criteria one takes to

govern one’s own theorizing, and consequently tacitly relying on

the idea that everyone already knows what counts as moral, can lead to

a number of problems. One, of course, is a conflation of morality with

other things (see Machery 2012 on Churchland 2011). Another is that

one mistakes one’s own cultural biases for universal truths

(Haidt and Kesiber 2010).

Because theorists in psychology and anthropology often need to design

questionnaires and other sorts of probes of the attitudes of subjects,

they might be expected to be more sensitive to the need for a

reasonably clear means of separating moral judgments from other sorts

of judgments. After all, examining the specifically moral judgments of

individuals is one of the most direct means of determining what the

moral code of a person or group might be. But despite this

expectation, and roughly half a century ago, Abraham Edel (1962: 56)

decried the lack of an explicit concern to delimit the domain of

morality among anthropologists, writing that “morality…is

taken for granted, in the sense that one can invoke it or refer to it

at will; but it is not explained, depicted, or analysed”. One

explanation for this that Edel suggested is the same as the

explanation for the same phenomenon in Philosophy: “it is

assumed that we all know what morality is and no explicit account need

be given”. But the danger for those making this assumption, he

points out, is that of “merging the morality concept with social

control concepts”. Reinforcing this tendency was the influence,

in anthropology, of the sociologist Émile Durkheim (1906

[2009]), for whom morality was simply a matter of how a given society

enforces whatever social rules it happens to have.

The failure to offer an operational definition of morality or moral

judgment may help explain the widespread but dubious assumption in

contemporary anthropology, noted by James Laidlaw (2016: 456), that

altruism is the essential and irreducible core of ethics. But Laidlaw

also notes that many of the features of what Bernard Williams (1985)

described as “the morality system”—features that

Williams himself criticized as the parochial result of a

secularization of Christian values—are in fact widely shared

outside of the West. This state of affairs leads Laidlaw to ask the

crucial question:

Which features, formal or substantive, are shared by the

“morality system” of the modern West and those of the

other major agrarian civilizations and literate religions?

This is, to a very close approximation, a request for the definition

of morality in the descriptive sense.

Klenk (2019) notes that in recent years anthropology has taken what he

terms an “ethical turn”, recognizing moral systems, and

ethics more generally, as a distinct object of anthropological study.

This is a move away from the Durkheimian paradigm, and includes the

study of self-development, virtues, habits, and the role of explicit

deliberation when moral breakdowns occur. However, Klenk’s

survey of attempts by anthropologists to study morality as an

independent domain lead him to conclude that, so far, their efforts do

not readily allow a distinction between moral considerations and other

normative considerations such as prudential, epistemic, or aesthetic

ones. (2019: 342)

In light of Edel’s worry about a conflation of moral systems

with systems of social control, it is interesting to consider Curry

(2016), who defends the hypothesis that

morality turns out to be a collection of biological and cultural

solutions to the problems of cooperation and conflict recurrent in

human social life. (2016: 29)

Curry notes that rules related to kinship, mutualism, exchange, and

various forms of conflict resolution appear in virtually all

societies. And he argues that many of them have precursors in animal

behavior, and can be explained by appeal to his central hypothesis of

morality as a solution to problems of cooperation and conflict

resolution. He also notes that philosophers, from Aristotle through

Hume, Russell, and Rawls, all took cooperation and conflict resolution

to be central ideas in understanding morality. It is unclear, however,

whether Curry’s view can adequately distinguish morality from

law and from other systems that aim to reduce conflict by providing

solutions to coordination problems.

Turning from anthropology to psychology, one significant topic of

investigation is the existence and nature of a distinction between the

moral and the conventional. More specifically, the distinction at

issue is between (a) acts that are judged wrong only because of a

contingent convention or because they go against the dictates of some

relevant authority, and (b) those that are judged to be wrong quite

independently of these things, that have a seriousness to them, and

that are justified by appeal to the notions of harm, rights, or

justice. Elliot Turiel emphasized this distinction, and drew attention

to the danger, if one overlooks it, of lumping together moral rules

with non-moral “conventions that further the coordination of

social interactions within social systems” (1983:

109–111). Those who accept this distinction are implicitly

offering a definition of morality in the descriptive sense. Not

everyone does accept the distinction, however. Edouard Machery and Ron

Mallon (2010) for example, are suspicious of the idea that

authority-independence, universality, justification by appeal to harm,

justice, or rights, and seriousness form a cluster found together with

sufficient regularity to be used to set moral norms apart from other

norms. Kelly et al. (2007) are similarly skeptical, and bring

empirical evidence to bear on the question.

The psychologist Kurt Gray might be seen as offering an account of

moral judgment that would allow us to determine the morality of an

individual or group. He and his co-authors suggest that

morality is essentially represented by a cognitive template that

combines a perceived intentional agent with a perceived suffering

patient. (Gray, Young, & Waytz 2012: 102)

This claim, while quite strong, is nevertheless not as implausibly

strong as it might seem, since the thesis is directly concerned with

the template we use when thinking about moral matters; it is

not directly concerned with the nature of morality itself. In the

sense of “template” at issue here, the template we use

when thinking about dogs might include having four legs, a tail, and

fur, among other things. But that does not mean that an animal must

have these features to count as a dog, or even that we believe

this.

Given the way that Gray et al. think of templates, even if their

hypothesis is correct, it would not mean that our psychology requires

us to think of the moral as always involving intentional agents and

perceiving patients. In line with this, and despite some lapses in

which they suggest that “moral acts can be defined in

terms of intention and suffering”, (2012: 109) their considered

view seems to be only that the dyadic template fits the

majority of moral situations, as we conceive them. Moreover,

the link between immoral behavior and suffering to which they appeal

in defending their general view is sometimes so indirect as to

undermine its significance. For example, they fit authority violations

into their suffering-based template by noting that “authority

structures provide a way of peacefully resolving conflict” and

that “violence results when social structures are

threatened”. In a similar stretch, they account for judgments

that promiscuity is wrong by gesturing at the suffering involved in

sexually transmitted diseases (2012: 107).

Another position in cognitive psychology that has relevance for the

definition of morality in the descriptive sense takes moral judgment

to be a natural kind: the product of an innate moral grammar (Mikhail

2007). If moral judgment is a natural kind in this way, then a

person’s moral code might simply consist in the moral judgments

that person is disposed to make. One piece of evidence that there is

such a grammar is to be found in the relative universality of certain

moral concepts in human cultures: concepts such as obligation,

permission, and prohibition. Another is an argument similar to

Chomsky’s famous “poverty of the stimulus” argument

for a universal human grammar (Dwyer et al. 2010; see also Roedder and

Harman 2010).

In evolutionary biology, morality is sometimes simply equated with

fairness (Baumard et al. 2013: 60, 77) or reciprocal altruism

(Alexander 1987: 77). But it is also sometimes identified by reference

to an evolved capacity to make a certain sort of judgment and perhaps

also to signal that one has made it (Hauser 2006). This also makes

morality into something very much like a natural kind, that can be

identified by reference to causal/historical processes. In that case,

a content-based definition of morality isn’t required: certain

central features are all that one needs to begin one’s

theorizing, since they will be enough to draw attention to certain

psychologically and biologically individuated mechanisms, and the

study of morality will be a detailed inquiry into the nature and

evolutionary history of these mechanisms.

4. Normative Definitions of “Morality”

Those who use “morality” normatively hold that morality is

(or would be) the behavioral code that meets the following condition:

all rational persons, under certain specified conditions, would

endorse it. Indeed, this is a plausible basic schema for definitions

of “morality” in the normative sense. Although some hold

that no code could meet the condition, many theorists hold that there

is one that does; we can call the former “moral skeptics”

and the latter “moral realists” (see entries on LINK:

moral skepticism and moral realism).

Many moral skeptics would reject the claim that there are any

universal ethical truths, where the ethical is a broader category than

the moral. But another interesting class of moral skeptics includes

those who think that we should only abandon the narrower category of

the moral—partly because of the notion of a code that

is central to that category. These moral skeptics hold that we should

do our ethical theorizing in terms of the good life, or the virtues.

Elizabeth Anscombe (1958) gave expression to this kind of view, which

also finds echoes in the work of Bernard Williams (1985). On the other

hand, some virtue theorists might take perfect rationality to entail

virtue, and might understand morality to be something like the code

that such a person would implicitly endorse by acting in virtuous

ways. In that case, even a virtue theorist might count as a moral

realist in the sense above.

Consequentialist views might not seem to fit the basic schema for

definitions of “morality” in the normative sense, since

they do not appear to make reference to the notions of endorsement or

rationality. But this appearance is deceptive. Mill himself explicitly

defines morality as

the rules and precepts for human conduct, by the observance of which

[a happy existence] might be, to the greatest extent possible,

secured. (1861 [2002: 12])

And he thinks that the mind is not in a “right state”

unless it is in “the state most conducive to the general

happiness”—in which case it would certainly favor morality

as just characterized. And the act-consequentialist J.J.C. Smart

(1956) is also explicit that he is thinking of ethics as the study of

how it is most rational to behave. His embrace of utilitarianism is

the result of his belief that maximizing utility is always the

rational thing to do. On reflection it is not surprising that many

moral theorists implicitly hold that the codes they offer would be

endorsed by all rational people, at least under certain conditions.

Unless one holds this, one will have to admit that, having been shown

that a certain behavior is morally required, a rational person might

simply shrug and ask “So what? What is that to me?” And,

though some exceptions are mentioned below, very few moral realists

think that their arguments leave this option open. Even fewer think

this option remains open if we are allowed to add some additional

conditions beyond mere rationality: a restriction on beliefs, for

example (similar to Rawls’ (1971: 118) veil of ignorance), or

impartiality.

Definitions of morality in the normative sense—and,

consequently, moral theories—differ in their accounts of

rationality, and in their specifications of the conditions under which

all rational persons would necessarily endorse the code of conduct

that therefore would count as morality. These definitions and theories

also differ in how they understand what it is to endorse a code in the

relevant way. Related to these differences, definitions of

“morality”—and moral theories—differ with

regard to those to whom morality applies: that is, those whose

behavior is subject to moral judgment. Some hold that morality applies

only to those rational beings that have certain specific features of

human beings: features that make it rational for them to endorse

morality. These features might, for example, include fallibility and

vulnerability. Other moral theories claim to put forward an account of

morality that provides a guide to all rational beings, even if these

beings do not have these human characteristics, e.g., God.

Among those who use “morality” normatively, virtually all

hold that “morality” refers to a code of conduct that

applies to all who can understand it and can govern their

behavior by it, though many hold that it protects a larger

group. Among such theorists it is also common to hold that morality

should never be overridden. That is, it is common to hold that no one

should ever violate a moral prohibition or requirement for non-moral

reasons. This claim is trivial if “should” is taken to

mean “morally should”. So the claim about moral

overridingness is typically understood with “should”

meaning “rationally should”, with the result that moral

requirements are asserted to be rational requirements. Though common,

this view is by no means always taken as definitional. Sidgwick (1874)

despaired of showing that rationality required us to choose

morality over egoism, though he certainly did not think rationality

required egoism either. More explicitly, Gert (2005) held that though

moral behavior is always rationally permissible, it is not

always rationally required. Foot (1972) seems to have held

that any reason—and therefore any rational requirement—to

act morally would have to stem from a contingent commitment or an

objective interest. And she also seems to have held that sometimes

neither of these sorts of reasons might be available, so that moral

behavior might not be rationally required for some agents. Finally,

moral realists who hold desire-based theories of reasons and formal,

means/end theories of rationality sometimes explicitly deny that moral

behavior is always even rationally permissible (Goldman

2009), and in fact this seems to be a consequence of Foot’s view

as well, though she does not emphasize it.

Despite the fact that theorists such as Sidgwick, Gert, Foot, and

Goldman do not hold that moral behavior is rationally required, they

are by no means precluded from using “morality” in the

normative sense. Using “morality” in the normative sense,

and holding that there is such a thing, only entails holding that

rational people would put a certain system forward; it does not entail

holding that rational people would always be motivated to follow that

system themselves. But to the degree that a theorist would deny even

the claim about endorsement, and hold instead that rational people

might not only fail to act morally, but might even reject it as a

public system, that theorist is either not using

“morality” in a normative sense, or is denying the

existence of morality in that sense. Such a theorist may also be using

“morality” in a descriptive sense, or may not have any

particular sense in mind.

When “morality” is used in its normative sense, it need

not have either of the two formal features that are essential to

moralities referred to by the descriptive sense: that it be a code of

conduct that is put forward by a society, group, or individual, or

that it be accepted as a guide to behavior by the members of that

society or group, or by that individual. Indeed, it is possible that

morality, in the normative sense, has never been put forward by any

particular society, by any group at all, or even by any individual.

This is partly a consequence of the fact that “morality”

in the normative sense is understood in terms of a conditional that is

likely to be counterfactual: it is the code that would be endorsed by

any fully rational person under certain conditions.

If one is a moral realist, and one also acknowledges the descriptive

sense of “morality”, one may require that descriptive

moralities at least approximate, in some ways, morality in the

normative sense. That is, one might claim that the guides to behavior

of some societies lack so many of the essential features of morality

in the normative sense, that it is incorrect to say that these

societies even have a morality in a descriptive sense. This is an

extreme view, however. A more moderate position would hold that all

societies have something that can be regarded as their morality, but

that many of these moralities—perhaps, indeed, all of

them—are defective. That is, a moral realist might hold that

although these actual guides to behavior have enough of the features

of normative morality to be classified as descriptive moralities, they

would not be endorsed in their entirety by all moral agents.

While moral realists do not claim that any actual society has or has

ever had morality as its actual guide to conduct, “natural

law” theories of morality claim that any rational person in any

society, even one that has a defective morality, is capable of knowing

what general kinds of actions morality prohibits, requires,

discourages, encourages, and allows. In the theological version of

natural law theories, such as that put forward by Aquinas, this is

because God implanted this knowledge in the reason of all persons. In

the secular version of natural law theories, such as that put forward

by Hobbes (1660), natural reason is sufficient to allow all rational

persons to know what morality prohibits, requires, etc. Natural law

theorists also claim that morality applies to all rational persons,

not only those now living, but also those who lived in the past.

In contrast to natural law theories, other moral theories do not hold

quite so strong a view about the universality of knowledge of

morality. Still, many hold that morality is known to all who can

legitimately be judged by it. Baier (1958), Rawls (1971) and

contractarians deny that there can be an esoteric morality:

one that judges people even though they cannot know what it prohibits,

requires, etc. For all of the above theorists, morality is what we can

call a public system: a system of norms (1) that is knowable

by all those to whom it applies and (2) that is not irrational for any

of those to whom it applies to follow (Gert 2005: 10). Moral judgments

of blame thus differ from legal or religious judgments of blame in

that they cannot be made about persons who are legitimately ignorant

of what they are required to do. Act consequentialists seem to hold

that everyone should know that they are morally required to act so as

to bring about the best consequences, but even they do not seem to

think judgments of moral blame are appropriate if a person is

legitimately ignorant of what action would bring about the best

consequences (Singer 1993: 228). Parallel views seem to be held by

rule consequentialists (Hooker 2001: 72).

The ideal situation for a legal system would be that it be a public

system. But in any large society this is not possible. Games are

closer to being public systems and most adults playing a game know its

rules, or they know that there are judges whose interpretation

determines what behavior the game prohibits, requires, etc. Although a

game is often a public system, its rules apply only to those playing

the game. If a person does not care enough about the game to abide by

the rules, she can usually quit. Morality is the one public system

that no rational person can quit. The fact that one cannot quit

morality means that one can do nothing to escape being legitimately

liable to sanction for violating its norms, except by ceasing to be a

moral agent. Morality applies to people simply by virtue of their

being rational persons who know what morality prohibits, requires,

etc., and being able to guide their behavior accordingly.

Public systems can be formal or informal. To say a

public system is informal is to say that it has no authoritative

judges and no decision procedure that provides a unique guide to

action in all situations, or that resolves all disagreements. To say

that a public system is formal is to say that it has one or both of

these things (Gert 2005: 9). Professional basketball is a formal

public system; all the players know that what the referees call a foul

determines what is a foul. Pickup basketball is an informal public

system. The existence of persistent moral disagreements shows that

morality is most plausibly regarded as an informal public system. This

is true even for such moral theories as the Divine Command theory and

act utilitarianism, inasmuch as there are no authoritative judges of

God’s will, or of which act will maximize utility, and there are

no decision procedures for determining these things (Scanlon 2011:

261–2). When persistent moral disagreement is recognized, those

who understand that morality is an informal public system admit that

how one should act is morally unresolvable, and if some resolution is

required, the political or legal system can be used to resolve it.

These formal systems have the means to provide unique guides, but they

do not provide the uniquely correct moral guide to the action that

should be performed.

An important example of a moral problem left unsettled by the informal

public system of morality is whether fetuses are impartially protected

by morality and so whether or under what conditions abortions are

allowed. There is continuing disagreement among fully informed moral

agents about this moral question, even though the legal and political

system in the United States has provided fairly clear guidelines about

the conditions under which abortion is legally allowed. Despite this

important and controversial issue, morality, like all informal public

systems, presupposes agreement on how to act in most moral situations,

e.g., all agree that killing or seriously harming any moral agent

requires strong justification in order to be morally allowed. No one

thinks it is morally justified to cheat, deceive, injure, or kill a

moral agent simply in order to gain sufficient money to take a

fantastic vacation. Moral matters are often thought to be

controversial because everyday decisions, about which there is no

controversy, are rarely discussed. The amount of agreement concerning

what rules are moral rules, and on when it is justified to violate one

of these rules, explains why morality can be a public system even

though it is an informal system.

By using the notion of an informal public system, we can improve the

basic schema for definitions of “morality” in the

normative sense. The old schema was that morality is the code

that all rational persons, under certain specified conditions, would

endorse. The improved schema is that morality is the informal

public system that all rational persons, under certain specified

conditions, would endorse. Some theorists might not regard the

informal nature of the moral system as definitional, holding that

morality might give knowable precise answers to every question. This

would have the result that conscientious moral agents often cannot

know what morality permits, requires, or allows. Some philosophers

deny that this is a genuine possibility.

On any definition of “morality”, whether descriptive or

normative, it is a code of conduct. However, on ethical- or

group-relativist accounts or on individualistic accounts—all of

which are best regarded as accounts of morality in the descriptive

sense—morality often has no special content that distinguishes

it from nonmoral codes of conduct, such as law or religion. Just as a

legal code of conduct can have almost any content, as long as it is

capable of guiding behavior, and a religious code of conduct has no

limits on content, most relativist and individualist accounts of

morality place few limits on the content of a moral code. Of course,

actual codes do have certain minimal limits—otherwise the

societies they characterize would lack the minimum required degree of

social cooperation required to sustain their existence over time. On

the other hand, for moral realists who explicitly hold that morality

is an informal public system that all rational persons would put

forward for governing the behavior of all moral agents, it has a

fairly definite content. Hobbes (1660), Mill (1861), and most other

non-religiously influenced philosophers in the Anglo-American

tradition limit morality to behavior that, directly or indirectly,

affects others.

The claim that morality only governs behavior that affects others is

somewhat controversial, and so probably should not be counted as

definitional of morality, even if it turns out to be entailed by the

correct moral theory. Some have claimed that morality also governs

behavior that affects only the agent herself, such as taking

recreational drugs, masturbation, and not developing one’s

talents. Kant (1785) may provide an account of this wide concept of

morality. Interpreted this way, Kant’s theory still fits the

basic schema, but includes these self-regarding moral requirements

because of the particular account of rationality he employs. However,

pace Kant, it is doubtful that all moral agents would put

forward a universal guide to behavior that governs behavior that does

not affect them at all. Indeed, when the concept of morality is

completely distinguished from religion, moral rules do seem to limit

their content to behavior that directly or indirectly causes or risks

harm to others. Some behavior that seems to affect only oneself, e.g.,

taking recreational drugs, may have a significant indirect harmful

effect on others by supporting the illegal and harmful activity of

those who benefit from the sale of those drugs.

Confusion about the content of morality sometimes arises because

morality is not distinguished sufficiently from religion. Regarding

self-affecting behavior as governed by morality is supported by the

idea that we are created by God and are obliged to obey God’s

commands, and so may be a holdover from the time when morality was not

clearly distinguished from religion. This religious holdover might

also affect the claim that some sexual practices such as homosexuality

are immoral. Those who clearly distinguish morality from religion

typically do not regard sexual orientation as a moral matter.

It is possible to hold that having a certain sort of social goal is

definitional of morality (Frankena 1963). Stephen Toulmin (1950) took

it to be the harmony of society. Baier (1958) took it to be “the

good of everyone alike”. Utilitarians sometimes claim it is the

production of the greatest good. Gert (2005) took it to be the

lessening of evil or harm. This latter goal may seem to be a

significant narrowing of the utilitarian claim, but utilitarians

always include the lessening of harm as essential to producing the

greatest good and almost all of their examples involve the avoiding or

preventing of harm. It is notable that the paradigm cases of moral

rules are those that prohibit causing harm directly or indirectly,

such as rules prohibiting killing, causing pain, deceiving, and

breaking promises. Even those precepts that require or encourage

positive action, such as helping the needy, are almost always related

to preventing or relieving harms, rather than promoting goods such as

pleasure.

Among the views of moral realists, differences in content are less

significant than similarities. For all such philosophers, morality

prohibits actions such as killing, causing pain, deceiving, and

breaking promises. For some, morality also requires charitable

actions, but failure to act charitably on every possible occasion does

not require justification in the same way that any act of killing,

causing pain, deceiving, and breaking promises requires justification.

Both Kant (1785) and Mill (1861) distinguish between duties of perfect

obligation and duties of imperfect obligation and regard not harming

as the former kind of duty and helping as the latter kind of duty. For

Gert (2005), morality encourages charitable action, but does not

require it; it is always morally good to be charitable, but it is not

immoral not to be charitable.

Even if the plausible basic schema for definitions of

“morality” in the normative sense is accepted, one’s

understanding of what morality is, in this sense, will still depend

very significantly on how one understands rationality. As has already

been mentioned, morality, in the normative sense, is sometimes taken

to prohibit certain forms of consensual sexual activity, or the use of

recreational drugs. But including such prohibitions in an account of

morality as a universal guide that all rational persons would put

forward requires a very particular view of rationality. After all,

many will deny that it is irrational to favor harmless consensual

sexual activities, or to favor the use of certain drugs for purely

recreational purposes.

One concept of rationality that supports the exclusion of sexual

matters, at least at the basic level, from the norms of morality, is

that for an action to count as irrational it must be an act that harms

oneself without producing a compensating benefit for

someone—perhaps oneself, perhaps someone else. Such an account

of rationality might be called “hybrid”, since it gives

different roles to self-interest and to altruism. An account of

morality based on the hybrid concept of rationality could agree with

Hobbes (1660) that morality is concerned with promoting people living

together in peace and harmony, which includes obeying the rules

prohibiting causing harm to others. Although moral prohibitions

against actions that cause harm or significantly increase the risk of

harm are not absolute, in order to avoid acting immorally,

justification is always needed when violating these prohibitions. Kant

(1797) seems to hold that it is never justified to violate some of

these prohibitions, e.g., the prohibition against lying. This is

largely a result of the fact that Kant’s (1785) concept of

rationality is purely formal, in contrast with the hybrid concept of

rationality described above.

Most moral realists who offer moral theories do not bother to offer

anything like a definition of morality. Instead, what these

philosophers offer is a theory of the nature and justification of a

set of norms with which they take their audience already to be

acquainted. In effect, they tacitly pick morality out by reference to

certain salient and relative uncontroversial bits of its content: that

it prohibits killing, stealing, deceiving, cheating, and so on. In

fact, this would not be a bad way of defining morality, if the point

of such a definition were only to be relatively theory-neutral, and to

allow theorizing to begin. We could call it “the

reference-fixing definition” or “the substantive

definition” (see Prinz and Nichols 2010: 122).

Some, including Hare (1952, 1963), have been tempted to argue against

the possibility of a substantive definition of morality, on the basis

of the claim that moral disapproval is an attitude that can be

directed at anything whatsoever. Foot (1958a, 1958b), argued against

this idea, but the substantive definition still has the drawback is

that it does not, somehow, seem to get at the essence of morality. One

might suggest that the substantive definition has the advantage of

including Divine Command theories of morality, while such theories

might seem to make trouble for definitions based on the plausible

schema given above. But it is plausible to hold that Divine Command

theories rest on Natural Law theories, which do in fact fit the

schema. Divine Command theories that do not rest on Natural Law might

make trouble for the schema, but one might also think that such

theories rest instead on a confusion, since they seem to entail that

God might have made it immoral to act beneficently.

5. Variations

As one gives more substance and detail to the general notions of

endorsement, rationality, and the relevant conditions under which

rational people would endorse morality, one moves further from

providing a definition of morality in the normative sense, and closer

to providing an actual moral theory. And a similar claim is true for

definitions of morality in the descriptive sense, as one specifies in

more detail what one means in claiming that a person or group endorses

a system or code. In the following four subsections, four broad ways

of making the definitions of morality more precise are presented. They

are all sufficiently schematic to be regarded as varieties of

definition, rather than as theories.

5.1 Morality as linked to norms for responses to behavior

Expressivists about morality do not take there to be any objective

content to morality that could underwrite what we above called

“the substantive definition”. Rather, they explicitly

recognize the existence of significant variation in what rules and

ideals different people put forward as morality in the normative

sense. And they doubt that this variation is compatible with moral

realism. Consequently, they need to offer some unifying features of

these different sets of rules and ideals, despite variation in their

content. As a result of this pressure, some expressivists end up

offering explicit accounts of a distinctively moral attitude

one might hold towards an act token or type. These accounts can of

course be taken to underwrite various forms of morality in the

descriptive sense. But they can also be taken to provide the basis of

one form of moral realism.

To see how an expressivist view can be co-opted by a moral realist of

a certain sort, consider Allan Gibbard’s (1990) moral

expressivism. Gibbard holds that moral judgments are expressions of

the acceptance of norms for feeling the emotions of guilt and anger.

One can accept Gibbard’s view of what it is to endorse a moral

claim without accepting the view that, in conflicts, all disagreements

are faultless. That is, even a moral realist can use Gibbard’s

view of the nature of moral judgment, and extract from it a definition

of morality. Used by such a theorist, Gibbard’s view entails

that morality, in the normative sense, is the code that is picked out

by the correct set of norms for feeling guilt and anger: that

is, the norms a rational person would endorse. This is

equivalent to accepting the plausible general schema for a definition

of “morality” given above, and understanding endorsement

in a special sense. To endorse a code in the relevant way, on this

definition, is to think that violations of its norms make guilt and

anger appropriate.

Closely related to Gibbard’s account is one according to which

the norms of relevance are not norms for the emotions, but are norms

for other reactions to behavior. For example, a person’s

morality might be the set of rules and ideals they regard as picked

out by appropriate norms for praise and blame, and other social

sanctions (Sprigge 1964: 317). In fact, reference to praise and blame

may be more adequate than reference to guilt and anger, since the

latter seem only to pick out moral prohibitions, and not to make room

for the idea that morality also recommends or encourages certain

behaviors even if it does not require them. For example, it is

plausible that there is such a thing as supererogatory action, and

that the specification of what counts as supererogatory is part of

morality—whether in the descriptive or normative sense. But it

does not seem likely that we can account for this part of morality by

appeal to norms for guilt and anger, and it is not at all clear that

there are emotions that are as closely linked to supererogation as

guilt and anger are to moral transgression. On the other hand, it

seems plausible that norms for praising action might help to pick out

what counts as supererogatory.

Another version of the present strategy would replace talk of praise

and blame with talk of reward and punishment. This view would take

morality to be a system that explained what kinds of actions are

appropriately rewarded and—more centrally—punished. This

sort of view, which remains closely related to Gibbard’s

suggestion, can also be regarded as fitting the general schema given

above. On this view, the notion of endorsing a code is unpacked in

terms of the acceptance of norms for reward and punishment. Skorupski

(1993), following Mill (1861), advocates a definition of morality

along these lines, though he then understands punishment primarily in

terms of blame, and understands blame as very closely linked to

emotion—indeed, merely having the emotion can count as

blaming—so that the resulting view is similar to Gibbard’s

in one important way, at least when one focuses on moral

wrongness.

It is certainly plausible that it is appropriate to feel guilt when

one acts immorally, and to feel anger at those who act immorally

towards those one cares about. It is even plausible that it is

only appropriate, in some particular sense of

“appropriate”, to feel guilt and anger in connection with

moral transgressions. So norms for guilt and anger may well uniquely

pick out certain moral norms. And similar claims might be made about

norms for praise and blame. However, it is not equally clear that

morality is properly defined in terms of emotions or other

reactions to behavior. For it may be, as Skorupski emphasizes, that we

need to understand guilt and anger, and praise and blame, in terms of

moral concepts. This worry about direction of explanation seems less

pressing for the notions of reward and punishment. These responses to

behavior, at least in themselves, might simply be understood

in terms of the meting out of benefits and harms. Of course they will

only count as reward and punishment when they are linked to

someone’s having followed or violated a rule that all rational

people would want to see enforced by such responses.

5.2 Morality as linked to advocacy of a code

One way of understanding the notion of endorsement is as advocacy.

Advocating a code is a second- or third-personal matter, since one

advocates a code to others. Moreover, it is consistent with advocating

a code, that one does not plan on following that code oneself. Just as

asserting something one believes to be false still counts as asserting

it, hypocritical advocacy of a code still counts as advocacy of that

code. When endorsement is understood as advocacy, it can be used in

definitions of morality, in the descriptive sense, as long as it is

the morality of a group or society. And advocacy can also be used as

an interpretation of endorsement when providing a definition of

morality in the normative sense. Of course those who accept a

definition of morality in any of these senses—as the code that a

group or society endorses, or as the code that would be universally

advocated by all rational agents under certain conditions—do not

hold that the advocacy would necessarily, or even probably, be

hypocritical. But they do hold that the important thing about a moral

code—what picks it out as a moral code—is that it would be

put forward by all the relevant agents, not that it would be

followed by all of them. The notion of advocacy has less of a

place in a descriptive account of a single person’s morality,

since when someone is hypocritical we often deny that they really hold

the moral view that they advocate.

Mill (1861), in addition to offering a moral theory, takes pains to

explain how morality differs from other normative systems. For him,

norms that simply promote utility are norms of expediency. In order to

qualify as morally wrong, an act must be one that ought to be

punished. Thinking that an act of a certain kind ought to be punished

is a third-personal matter, so it seems plausible to put Mill’s

view of what is definitional of morality into the category being

discussed in this section. It is worth noting that hypocrisy is, for

Mill, not only a possibility, but—given the present sorry state

of moral education—virtually unavoidable. That is because being

motivated to advocate punishment for a certain kind of act is quite

different from being motivated to refrain from that same kind of act.

Advocating punishment for a certain kind of act might be one’s

utility-maximizing choice, while actually performing that kind of act

(trying, of course, to avoid detection) might also be

utility-maximizing. And for Mill what determines what a person will

advocate, and how a person will act, are the foreseeable consequences

for that person.

Bernard Gert’s (2005) moral view also operates with a definition

of morality that understands endorsement as advocacy, in the sense of

putting forward as a guide for all rational agents. Gert offers the

following two conditions as those under which all rational persons

would put forward a universal guide for governing the behavior of all

moral agents. The first condition is that they are seeking agreement

with all other rational persons or moral agents. The second condition

is that they use only those beliefs that are shared by all rational

persons: for example, that they themselves are fallible and vulnerable

and that all those to whom morality applies are also fallible and

vulnerable. The second condition rules out both religious beliefs and

scientific beliefs since there are no religious beliefs or scientific

beliefs that all rational persons share. This condition is plausible

because no universal guide to behavior that applies to all rational

persons can be based on beliefs that some of these rational persons do

not share.

5.3 Morality as linked to acceptance of a code

Another way of understanding the notion of endorsement is as

acceptance. Unlike advocating a code, accepting a code is a

first-personal matter. It might include intending to conform

one’s own behavior to that code, feeling guilty when one does

not, and so on. One cannot hypocritically accept a code. Indeed,

hypocrisy is simply a matter of advocating a code one does not accept.

So this notion of endorsement is available to someone who is trying to

provide a definition of morality in the descriptive sense, even when

considering a single person’s morality.

Paradigmatic views in the natural law tradition starting with Aquinas

hold both that the laws of morality have their source in God, and that

these laws constitute the principles of human practical rationality

(Finnis 1980; MacIntyre 1999). Views in this tradition may be seen as

using the basic schema for definitions of morality in the normative

sense, understanding endorsement as acceptance. Members of this

tradition typically hold that all rational persons know what kinds of

actions morality prohibits, requires, discourages, encourages, and

allows. It is central to Aquinas’s view that morality is known

to all those whose behavior is subject to moral judgment, even if they

do not know of the revelations of Christianity. This is why Aquinas

holds that knowing what morality prohibits and requires does not

involve knowing why morality prohibits and requires what it does.

Those who belong to the natural law tradition also hold that reason

endorses acting morally. This sort of endorsement of course has a

cognitive component. But it is also motivational. Aquinas does not

hold that knowledge of morality is always effective: it can be blotted

out by evil persuasions or corrupt habits. But if reason is not

opposed by such forces, any rational person would not only know what

was prohibited and required by morality, but would follow those

prohibitions and requirements. So, for natural law theorists,

endorsement amounts to acceptance.

5.4 Morality as linked to justification to others

The lack of an explicit and widely accepted definition of morality may

partially explain the resilience of act-consequentialist accounts of

morality. Without an explicit definition, it may be easier to ignore

the fact that act-consequentialist theories are not particularly

concerned with interpersonal interactions, but typically apply just as

well to desert island scenarios as to individuals who live in

societies. In any case, it has been recognized that in order to combat

consequentialism, it would be helpful to have something like a

plausible definition of morality that made it clear that the subject

matter of morality is something different from simply the goodness and

badness of consequences. T.M. Scanlon (1982, 1998), applying this

strategy, suggests that the subject matter of morality—what we

are talking about, when we talk about morality—is a system of

rules for the regulation of behavior that is not reasonably rejectable

based on a desire for informed unforced general agreement.

Scanlon’s suggestion regarding the subject matter of morality

can easily be seen as an instance of the general schema given above.

His “system of rules” is a specific kind of informal

public system; he understands endorsement by all rational people as

non-rejection by all reasonable people; and he offers a specific

account of the conditions under which moral agents would reach the

relevant agreement. But Scanlon also places very heavy emphasis on the

fact that if he is right about the subject matter of morality, then

what compliance with moral norms allows us to do is to justify our

behavior to others in ways that they cannot reasonably reject. Indeed,

the ability to justify ourselves to reasonable people is a primary

source of moral motivation for Scanlon (see also Sprigge 1964: 319).

This might seem to suggest a somewhat different definitional claim

about morality: that morality consists in the most basic norms in

terms of which we justify ourselves to others. But it is plausible

that this purportedly definitional claim is better thought of as a

corollary of Scanlon’s particular version of the general schema,

with endorsement understood as non-rejection. For, if morality is the

system of norms that would be endorsed in this way, we can justify our

actions to others by pointing out that even they, were they

reasonable, would have endorsed rules that allowed our behavior.

Stephen Darwall’s (2006) moral view can also be seen as flowing

from a version of the general schema, and yielding claims about

justifiability to others. Darwall claims that morality is a matter of equal accountability among free and rational beings. On his view, I

behave morally towards you to the degree that I respect the claims you

have authority to make on me. Darwall also holds that I will respect

those claims if I acknowledge certain assumptions to which I am

committed simply in virtue of being a rational, deliberating agent. As

a result, his view is that morality—or at least the morality of

obligation—is a “scheme of accountability” (a

certain sort of informal public system) that all rational people will

endorse. Unlike Scanlon’s view, however, Darwall’s view

makes use of a stronger sense of endorsement than non-rejection.

Specifically, it includes the recognition of the reasons provided by

the authoritative demands of other people. And that recognition is

positively motivational.

Both Scanlon’s and Darwall’s views emphasize the social

nature of morality, taken in the normative sense: Scanlon, by

reference to justification to others; Darwall, by appeal to the

relevance of second-personal reasons. But Darwall builds a

responsiveness to second-personal reasons into the relevant notion of

rationality, while Scanlon simply makes the empirical claim that many

people are motivated by a desire to justify themselves to others, and

notes that his definition of morality will yield rules that will allow

one to do this, if one follows them. The sort of definition described

in

section 5.1

also makes the social nature of morality essential to it, since it

centrally features the notion of a response to the behavior of others.

The definitions described in sections

5.2

and

5.3

do not entail the social nature of morality, since it is

possible to accept, and even to advocate, a code that concerns only

self-regarding behavior. But on any plausible account of rationality a

code that would be advocated by all moral agents will govern

interpersonal interactions, and will include rules that prohibit

causing harm without sufficient reason. Only the definition offered in

section 5.3

therefore can be taken as realistically compatible with an egoistic

morality.

Bibliography

Alexander, Richard, 1987, The Biology of Moral Systems,

New York: Routledge.

Anscombe, G. E. M., 1958, “Modern Moral Philosophy”,

Philosophy, 33(124): 1–19.

doi:10.1017/S0031819100037943

Aquinas, Thomas, c.1270, Summa Theologiae, Paris.

Baier, Kurt, 1958, The Moral Point of View, Ithaca, NY:

Cornell University Press.

Baumard, Nicolas, Jean-Baptiste André, and Dan Sperber,

2013, “A Mutualistic Approach to Morality: The Evolution of

Fairness by Partner Choice”, Behavioral and Brain

Sciences, 36(1): 59–78. doi:10.1017/S0140525X11002202

Bentham, Jeremy, 1789, An Introduction to the Principles of

Morals and Legislation, New York: Prometheus Books, 1988.

Brink, David, 1997, “Kantian Rationalism: Inescapability,

Authority, and Supremacy”, in Ethics and Practical

Reason, Garrett Cullity and Berys Gaut (eds.), Oxford: Oxford

University Press, pp. 255–291.

Churchland, Patricia, 2011, Braintrust: What Neuroscience

Tells Us About Morality, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University

Press.

Curry, Oliver Scott, 2016, “Morality as Cooperation: A

Problem-Centred Approach”, in The Evolution of

Morality, Todd K. Shackelford and Ranald Hansen (eds.), Cham:

Springer, pp. 27–51. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-19671-8_2

Darwall, Stephen, 2006, The Second-person Standpoint:

Morality, Respect, and Accountability, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

De Waal, Frans, 1996, Good Natured: The Origins of Right and

Wrong in Humans and Other Animals, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

Doris, John M. and The Moral Psychology Research Group (eds.),

2010, The Moral Psychology Handbook, Oxford: Oxford

University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199582143.001.0001

Durkheim, Émile, 1906 [2009], “La

Détermination du fait moral”. Collected in Sociologie

et Philosophie, Paris: Félix Alcan, 1924. Translated as

“The Determination of Moral Facts” in Sociology and

Philosophy, David Pocock (ed. and trans.), 1953, Reprinted

Routledge revivals. London: Routledge, 2009, pp. 16–31.

Dworkin, Ronald, 1986, Law’s Empire, Cambridge, MA:

Belknap Press.

Dwyer, Susan, Bryce Huebner, and Marc D. Hauser, 2010, “The

Linguistic Analogy: Motivations, Results, and Speculations”,

Topics in Cognitive Science, 2(3): 486–510.

doi:10.1111/j.1756-8765.2009.01064.x

Edel, Abraham, 1962, “Anthropology and Ethics in Common

Focus”, The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute

of Great Britain and Ireland, 92(1): 55–72.

doi:10.2307/2844321

Finnis, John, 1980, Natural Law and Natural Rights,

Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Foot, Philippa, 1958a, “Moral Beliefs”,

Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 59: 83–104.

doi:10.1093/aristotelian/59.1.83

–––, 1958b, “Moral Arguments”,

Mind, 67(268): 502–513.

doi:10.1093/mind/LXVII.268.502

–––, 1972, “Morality as a System of

Hypothetical Imperatives”, The Philosophical Review,

81(3): 305–316. doi:10.2307/2184328

Frankena, William, 1963, “Recent Conceptions of

Morality”, in G. Nakhnikian and H. Castañeda (eds.),

Morality and the Language of Conduct, Detroit, MI: Wayne

State University Press, pp. 1–24.

–––, 1973, Ethics, Englewood Cliffs,

N.J.: Prentice-Hall.

–––, 1980, Thinking about Morality, Ann

Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.

Gert, Bernard, 2005, Morality: Its Nature and

Justification, Revised Edition, New York: Oxford University

Press.

Gibbard, Allan, 1990, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings,

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Goldman, Alan H., 2009, Reasons from Within: Desires and

Values, New York: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199576906.001.0001

Gray, Kurt, Liane Young, and Adam Waytz, 2012, “Mind

Perception Is the Essence of Morality”, Psychological

Inquiry, 23(2): 101–124.

doi:10.1080/1047840X.2012.651387

Greene, Joshua, 2013, Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and The

Gap between Us and Them, New York: Penguin.

Haidt, Jonathan, 2006, The Happiness Hypothesis: Finding

Modern Truth in Ancient Wisdom, New York: Basic Books.

–––, 2011, The Righteous Mind: Why Good

People Are Divided by Politics and Religion, New York:

Pantheon.

Haidt, Jonathan and Selin Kesebir, 2010, “Morality”,

in S. Fiske, D. Gilbert, and G. Lindzey (eds.), Handbook of Social

Psychology, 5th Edition, Hobeken, NJ: Wiley, pp.

797–832.

Hare, R.M., 1952, The Language of Morals, New York:

Oxford University Press.

–––, 1963, Freedom and Reason, New

York: Oxford University Press.

–––, 1981, Moral Thinking, New York:

Oxford University Press.

Harman, Gilbert, 1975, “Moral Relativism Defended”,

The Philosophical Review, 84(1): 3–22.

doi:10.2307/2184078

Hauser, Marc, 2006, Moral Minds: How Nature Designed our

Universal Sense of Right and Wrong, New York: Harper

Collins.

Hobbes, Thomas, 1660 [1994], Leviathan, edited by Edwin

Curly, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994.

–––, 1658 and 1651 [1991], Man and

Citizen, (translations of six chapters of De Homine

(1658) and all of De Cive (1651)), edited by Bernard Gert,

Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1991.

Hooker, Brad, 2001, Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule

Consequentialist theory of Morality, Oxford: Clarendon

Press.

Hume, David, 1751 [1975], Enquiries concerning Human

Understanding and concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by

L.A. Selby-Bigge, 3rd edition revised by P.H. Nidditch,

Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.

Kant, Immanuel, 1785 and 1797 [1993], Groundwork of the

Metaphysics of Morals: with On a Supposed Right to Lie because of

Philanthropic Concerns, 3rd edition, translated by J.

Ellington, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993.

Kelly, Daniel, Stephen Stich, Kevin J. Haley, Serena J. Eng, and

Daniel M. T. Fessler, 2007, “Harm, Affect, and the

Moral/Conventional Distinction”, Mind & Language,

22(2): 117–131. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2007.00302.x

Klenk, Michael, 2019, “Moral Philosophy and the

‘Ethical Turn’ in Anthropology”, Zeitschrift

Für Ethik Und Moralphilosophie, 2(2): 331–353.

doi:10.1007/s42048-019-00040-9

Laidlaw, James, 2016, “The Interactional Foundations of

Ethics and the Formation and Limits of Morality Systems”,

HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory, 6(1): 455–461.

doi:10.14318/hau6.1.024

Liao, S. Matthew (ed.), 2016, Moral Brains. The Neuroscience

of Morality, New York: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199357666.001.0001

–––, 1999, Dependent Rational Animals,

Chicago: Open Court.

Machery, Edouard, 2012, “Delineating the Moral

Domain”, Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition,

Logic and Communication, 7(1): 1–14.

doi:10.4148/biyclc.v7i0.1777

Machery, Edouard and Ron Mallon, 2010, “The Evolution of

Morality”, in Doris and The Moral Psychology Research Group

2010: 3–46.

MacIntyre, Alasdair, 1957, “What Morality Is Not”,

Philosophy, 32(123): 325–335.

doi:10.1017/S0031819100051950

–––, 1999, Dependent Rational Animals,

Chicago: Open Court.

Mikhail, John, 2007, “Universal Moral Grammar: Theory,

Evidence and the Future”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences,

11(4): 143–152. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2006.12.007

Mill, John Stuart, 1861 [2002], Utilitarianism, edited by

G. Sher, Indianapolis: Hackett, 2002.

Moore, G.E., 1912, Ethics, New York: H. Holt.

–––, 1903, Principia Ethica, New York:

Cambridge University Press, 1993.

Prinz, Jesse, 2007, The Emotional Construction of Morals,

Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Prinz, Jesse and Shaun Nichols, 2010, “Moral

Emotions”, in Doris and The Moral Psychology Research Group

2010: 111–146.

Rawls, John, 1971, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA:

Harvard University Press.

Roedder, Erica and Gilbert Harman, 2010, “Linguistics and

Moral Theory”, in Doris and The Moral Psychology Research Group

2010: 273–296.

Scanlon, T. M., 1982, “Contractualism and

Utilitarianism”, in Utilitarianism and Beyond, Amartya

Sen and Bernard Williams (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 103–128. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511611964.007

–––, 1998, What We Owe to Each Other,

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

–––, 2011, “What is Morality?” in J.

Shephard, S. Kosslyn, and E. Hammonds (eds.), The Harvard Sampler:

Liberal Education for the Twenty-First Century, Cambridge, MA:

Harvard University Press, pp. 243–66.

Sidgwick, Henry, 1874, Methods of Ethics, Indianapolis:

Hackett Pub. Co., 1981.

Singer, Peter, 1993, Practical Ethics, 2nd

Edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (ed.), 2008, Moral Psychology Volume

1, The Evolution of Morality: Adaptations and Innateness,

Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

–––, 2016, “The Disunity of

Morality”, in Liao 2016: 331–354.

Skorupski, John, 1993, “The Definition of Morality”,

Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 35: 121–144.

doi:10.1017/S1358246100006299

Smart, J. J. C., 1956, “Extreme and Restricted

Utilitarianism”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 6(25):

344–354. doi:10.2307/2216786

Smith, Michael, 1994, The Moral Problem, Oxford:

Blackwell.

Sprigge, Timothy L. S., 1964, “Definition of a Moral

Judgment”, Philosophy, 39(150): 301–322.

doi:10.1017/S0031819100055777

Strawson, P. F., 1961, “Social Morality and Individual

Ideal”, Philosophy, 36(136): 1–17.

doi:10.1017/S003181910005779X

Thomson, J.J. and G. Dworkin (eds.), 1968, Ethics, New

York: Harper & Row.

Toulmin, Stephen, 1950, An Examination of the Place of Reason

in Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Turiel, Elliot, 1983, The Development of Social Knowledge:

Morality and Convention, Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Warnock, Geoffrey, 1971, The Object of Morality, London:

Methuen.

Westermarck, Edward, 1960, Ethical Relativity, Paterson,

N.J.: Littlefield, Adams.

Williams, Bernard, 1985, Ethics and the Limits of

Philosophy, London: Fontana.

Wong, David B., 1984, Moral Relativity, Berkeley CA:

University of California Press.

–––, 2006, Natural Moralities: A Defense of

Pluralistic Relativism, New York: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/0195305396.001.0001

–––, 2014, “Integrating Philosophy with

Anthropology in an Approach to Morality”, Anthropological

Theory, 14(3): 336–355. doi:10.1177/1463499614534554

Wren, T.E. (ed.), 1990, The Moral Domain: Essays in the

Ongoing Discussion Between Philosophy and the Social Sciences,

Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Academic Tools

How to cite this entry.

Preview the PDF version of this entry at the

Friends of the SEP Society.

Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry

at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).

Enhanced bibliography for this entry

at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Related Entries

consequentialism |

ethics: natural law tradition |

Hobbes, Thomas: moral and political philosophy |

Kant, Immanuel |

Mill, John Stuart |

moral realism |

moral relativism |

moral skepticism

Copyright © 2020 by

Bernard Gert

Joshua Gert

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.

The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support

Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

Browse

Table of Contents

What's New

Random Entry

Chronological

Archives

About

Editorial Information

About the SEP

Editorial Board

How to Cite the SEP

Special Characters

Advanced Tools

Accessibility

Contact

Support SEP

Support the SEP

PDFs for SEP Friends

Make a Donation

SEPIA for Libraries

Mirror Sites

View this site from another server:

USA (Main Site)

Philosophy, Stanford University

Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Aristotle’s Ethics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Aristotle’s Ethics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Menu

Browse

Table of Contents

What's New

Random Entry

Chronological

Archives

About

Editorial Information

About the SEP

Editorial Board

How to Cite the SEP

Special Characters

Advanced Tools

Contact

Support SEP

Support the SEP

PDFs for SEP Friends

Make a Donation

SEPIA for Libraries

Entry Navigation

Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic Tools

Friends PDF Preview

Author and Citation Info

Back to Top

Aristotle’s EthicsFirst published Tue May 1, 2001; substantive revision Sat Jul 2, 2022

Aristotle conceives of ethical theory as a field distinct from the

theoretical sciences. Its methodology must match its subject

matter—good action—and must respect the fact that in this

field many generalizations hold only for the most part. We study

ethics in order to improve our lives, and therefore its principal

concern is the nature of human well-being. Aristotle follows Socrates

and Plato in taking the virtues to be central to a well-lived life.

Like Plato, he regards the ethical virtues (justice, courage,

temperance and so on) as complex rational, emotional and social

skills. But he rejects Plato’s idea that to be completely

virtuous one must acquire, through a training in the sciences,

mathematics, and philosophy, an understanding of what goodness is.

What we need, in order to live well, is a proper appreciation of the

way in which such goods as friendship, pleasure, virtue, honor and

wealth fit together as a whole. In order to apply that general

understanding to particular cases, we must acquire, through proper

upbringing and habits, the ability to see, on each occasion, which

course of action is best supported by reasons. Therefore practical

wisdom, as he conceives it, cannot be acquired solely by learning

general rules. We must also acquire, through practice, those

deliberative, emotional, and social skills that enable us to put our

general understanding of well-being into practice in ways that are

suitable to each occasion.

1. Preliminaries

2. The Human Good and the Function Argument

3. Methodology

3.1 Traditional Virtues and the Skeptic

3.2 Differences from and Affinities to Plato

4. Virtues and Deficiencies, Continence and Incontinence

5. The Doctrine of the Mean

5.1 Ethical Virtue as Disposition

5.2 Ethical Theory Does Not Offer a Decision Procedure

5.3 The Starting Point for Practical Reasoning

6. Intellectual Virtues

7. Akrasia

8. Pleasure

9. Friendship

10. Three Lives Compared

Glossary

Further Reading

A. Single-Authored Overviews

B. Anthologies

C. Studies of Particular Topics

C.1 The Chronological Order of Aristotle’s Ethical Treatises

C.2 The Methodology and Metaphysics of Ethical Theory

C.3 The Human Good and the Human Function

C.4 The Nature of Virtue and Accounts of Particular Virtues

C.5 Practical Reasoning, Moral Psychology, and Action

C.6 Pleasure

C.7 Friendship

C.8 Feminism and Aristotle

C.9 Aristotle and Contemporary Ethics

D. Bibliographies

Bibliography

Primary Literature

Secondary Literature

Academic Tools

Other Internet Resources

Related Entries

1. Preliminaries

Aristotle wrote two ethical treatises: the Nicomachean Ethics

and the Eudemian Ethics. He does not himself use either of

these titles, although in the Politics (1295a36) he refers

back to one of them—probably the Eudemian

Ethics—as “ta êthika”—his

writings about character. The words “Eudemian”

and “Nicomachean” were added later, perhaps

because the former was edited by his friend, Eudemus, and the latter

by his son, Nicomachus. In any case, these two works cover more or

less the same ground: they begin with a discussion of

eudaimonia (“happiness”,

“flourishing”), and turn to an examination of the nature

of aretê (“virtue”,

“excellence”) and the character traits that human beings

need in order to live life at its best. Both treatises examine the

conditions in which praise or blame are appropriate, and the nature of

pleasure and friendship; near the end of each work, we find a brief

discussion of the proper relationship between human beings and the

divine.

Though the general point of view expressed in each work is the same,

there are many subtle differences in organization and content as well.

Clearly, one is a re-working of the other, and although no single

piece of evidence shows conclusively what their order is, it is widely

assumed that the Nicomachean Ethics is a later and improved

version of the Eudemian Ethics. (Not all of the Eudemian

Ethics was revised: its Books IV, V, and VI re-appear as V, VI,

VII of the Nicomachean Ethics.) Perhaps the most telling

indication of this ordering is that in several instances the

Nicomachean Ethics develops a theme about which its

Eudemian cousin is silent. Only the Nicomachean

Ethics discusses the close relationship between ethical inquiry

and politics; only the Nicomachean Ethics critically examines

Solon’s paradoxical dictum that no man should be counted happy

until he is dead; and only the Nicomachean Ethics gives a

series of arguments for the superiority of the philosophical life to

the political life. The remainder of this article will therefore focus

on this work. [Note: Page and line numbers shall henceforth refer to

this treatise.]

A third treatise, called the Magna Moralia (the “Big

Ethics”) is included in complete editions of Aristotle’s

works, but its authorship is disputed by scholars. It ranges over

topics discussed more fully in the other two works and its point of

view is similar to theirs. (Why, being briefer, is it named the

Magna Moralia? Because each of the two papyrus rolls into

which it is divided is unusually long. Just as a big mouse can be a

small animal, two big chapters can make a small book. This work was

evidently named “big” with reference to its parts, not the

whole.) A few authors in antiquity refer to a work with this name and

attribute it to Aristotle, but it is not mentioned by several

authorities, such as Cicero and Diogenes Laertius, whom we would

expect to have known of it. Some scholars hold that it is

Aristotle’s earliest course on ethics—perhaps his own

lecture notes or those of a student; others regard it as a

post-Aristotelian compilation or adaption of one or both of his

genuine ethical treatises.

Although Aristotle is deeply indebted to Plato’s moral

philosophy, particularly Plato’s central insight that moral

thinking must be integrated with our emotions and appetites, and that

the preparation for such unity of character should begin with

childhood education, the systematic character of Aristotle’s

discussion of these themes was a remarkable innovation. No one had

written ethical treatises before Aristotle. Plato’s

Republic, for example, does not treat ethics as a distinct

subject matter; nor does it offer a systematic examination of the

nature of happiness, virtue, voluntariness, pleasure, or friendship.

To be sure, we can find in Plato’s works important discussions

of these phenomena, but they are not brought together and unified as

they are in Aristotle’s ethical writings.

2. The Human Good and the Function Argument

The principal idea with which Aristotle begins is that there are

differences of opinion about what is best for human beings, and that

to profit from ethical inquiry we must resolve this disagreement. He

insists that ethics is not a theoretical discipline: we are asking

what the good for human beings is not simply because we want to have

knowledge, but because we will be better able to achieve our good if

we develop a fuller understanding of what it is to flourish. In

raising this question—what is the good?—Aristotle is not

looking for a list of items that are good. He assumes that such a list

can be compiled rather easily; most would agree, for example, that it

is good to have friends, to experience pleasure, to be healthy, to be

honored, and to have such virtues as courage at least to some degree.

The difficult and controversial question arises when we ask whether

certain of these goods are more desirable than others.

Aristotle’s search for the good is a search for the

highest good, and he assumes that the highest good, whatever

it turns out to be, has three characteristics: it is desirable for

itself, it is not desirable for the sake of some other good, and all

other goods are desirable for its sake.

Aristotle thinks everyone will agree that the terms

“eudaimonia” (“happiness”) and

“eu zên” (“living well”)

designate such an end. The Greek term “eudaimon”

is composed of two parts: “eu” means

“well” and “daimon” means

“divinity” or “spirit”. To be

eudaimon is therefore to be living in a way that is

well-favored by a god. But Aristotle never calls attention to this

etymology in his ethical writings, and it seems to have little

influence on his thinking. He regards “eudaimon”

as a mere substitute for eu zên (“living

well”). These terms play an evaluative role, and are not simply

descriptions of someone’s state of mind.

No one tries to live well for the sake of some further goal; rather,

being eudaimon is the highest end, and all

subordinate goals—health, wealth, and other such

resources—are sought because they promote well-being, not

because they are what well-being consists in. But unless we can

determine which good or goods happiness consists in, it is of little

use to acknowledge that it is the highest end. To resolve this issue,

Aristotle asks what the ergon (“function”,

“task”, “work”) of a human being is, and

argues that it consists in activity of the rational part of the soul

in accordance with virtue (1097b22–1098a20). One important

component of this argument is expressed in terms of distinctions he

makes in his psychological and biological works. The soul is analyzed

into a connected series of capacities: the nutritive soul is

responsible for growth and reproduction, the locomotive soul for

motion, the perceptive soul for perception, and so on. The biological

fact Aristotle makes use of is that human beings are the only species

that has not only these lower capacities but a rational soul as well.

The good of a human being must have something to do with being human;

and what sets humanity off from other species, giving us the potential

to live a better life, is our capacity to guide ourselves by using

reason. If we use reason well, we live well as human beings; or, to be

more precise, using reason well over the course of a full life is what

happiness consists in. Doing anything well requires virtue or

excellence, and therefore living well consists in activities caused by

the rational soul in accordance with virtue or excellence.

Aristotle’s conclusion about the nature of happiness is in a

sense uniquely his own. No other writer or thinker had said precisely

what he says about what it is to live well. But at the same time his

view is not too distant from a common idea. As he himself points out,

one traditional conception of happiness identifies it with virtue

(1098b30–1). Aristotle’s theory should be construed as a

refinement of this position. He says, not that happiness is virtue,

but that it is virtuous activity. Living well consists in

doing something, not just being in a certain state or condition. It

consists in those lifelong activities that actualize the virtues of

the rational part of the soul.

At the same time, Aristotle makes it clear that in order to be happy

one must possess others goods as well—such goods as friends,

wealth, and power. And one’s happiness is endangered if one is

severely lacking in certain advantages—if, for example, one is

extremely ugly, or has lost children or good friends through death

(1099a31–b6). But why so? If one’s ultimate end should

simply be virtuous activity, then why should it make any difference to

one’s happiness whether one has or lacks these other types of

good? Aristotle’s reply is that one’s virtuous activity

will be to some extent diminished or defective, if one lacks an

adequate supply of other goods (1153b17–19). Someone who is

friendless, childless, powerless, weak, and ugly will simply not be

able to find many opportunities for virtuous activity over a long

period of time, and what little he can accomplish will not be of great

merit. To some extent, then, living well requires good fortune;

happenstance can rob even the most excellent human beings of

happiness. Nonetheless, Aristotle insists, the highest good, virtuous

activity, is not something that comes to us by chance. Although we

must be fortunate enough to have parents and fellow citizens who help

us become virtuous, we ourselves share much of the responsibility for

acquiring and exercising the virtues.

3. Methodology

3.1 Traditional Virtues and the Skeptic

A common complaint about Aristotle’s attempt to defend his

conception of happiness is that his argument is too general to show

that it is in one’s interest to possess any of the particular

virtues as they are traditionally conceived. Suppose we grant, at

least for the sake of argument, that doing anything well, including

living well, consists in exercising certain skills; and let us call

these skills, whatever they turn out to be, virtues. Even so, that

point does not by itself allow us to infer that such qualities as

temperance, justice, courage, as they are normally understood, are

virtues. They should be counted as virtues only if it can be shown

that actualizing precisely these skills is what happiness consists in.

What Aristotle owes us, then, is an account of these traditional

qualities that explains why they must play a central role in any

well-lived life.

But perhaps Aristotle disagrees, and refuses to accept this

argumentative burden. In one of several important methodological

remarks he makes near the beginning of the Nicomachean

Ethics, he says that in order to profit from the sort of study he

is undertaking, one must already have been brought up in good habits

(1095b4–6). The audience he is addressing, in other words,

consists of people who are already just, courageous, and generous; or,

at any rate, they are well on their way to possessing these virtues.

Why such a restricted audience? Why does he not address those who have

serious doubts about the value of these traditional qualities, and who

therefore have not yet decided to cultivate and embrace them?

Addressing the moral skeptic, after all, is the project Plato

undertook in the Republic: in Book I he rehearses an argument

to show that justice is not really a virtue, and the remainder of this

work is an attempt to rebut this thesis. Aristotle’s project

seems, at least on the surface, to be quite different. He does not

appear to be addressing someone who has genuine doubts about the value

of justice or kindred qualities. Perhaps, then, he realizes how little

can be accomplished, in the study of ethics, to provide it with a

rational foundation. Perhaps he thinks that no reason can be given for

being just, generous, and courageous. These are qualities one learns

to love when one is a child, and having been properly habituated, one

no longer looks for or needs a reason to exercise them. One can show,

as a general point, that happiness consists in exercising some skills

or other, but that the moral skills of a virtuous person are what one

needs is not a proposition that can be established on the basis of

argument.

This is not the only way of reading the Ethics, however. For

surely we cannot expect Aristotle to show what it is about the

traditional virtues that makes them so worthwhile until he has fully

discussed the nature of those virtues. He himself warns us that his

initial statement of what happiness is should be treated as a rough

outline whose details are to be filled in later (1098a20–22).

His intention in Book I of the Ethics is to indicate in a

general way why the virtues are important; why particular

virtues—courage, justice, and the like—are components of

happiness is something we should be able to better understand only at

a later point.

In any case, Aristotle’s assertion that his audience must

already have begun to cultivate the virtues need not be taken to mean

that no reasons can be found for being courageous, just, and generous.

His point, rather, may be that in ethics, as in any other study, we

cannot make progress towards understanding why things are as they are

unless we begin with certain assumptions about what is the case.

Neither theoretical nor practical inquiry starts from scratch. Someone

who has made no observations of astronomical or biological phenomena

is not yet equipped with sufficient data to develop an understanding

of these sciences. The parallel point in ethics is that to make

progress in this sphere we must already have come to enjoy doing what

is just, courageous, generous and the like. We must experience these

activities not as burdensome constraints, but as noble, worthwhile,

and enjoyable in themselves. Then, when we engage in ethical inquiry,

we can ask what it is about these activities that makes them

worthwhile. We can also compare these goods with other things that are

desirable in themselves—pleasure, friendship, honor, and so

on—and ask whether any of them is more desirable than the

others. We approach ethical theory with a disorganized bundle of likes

and dislikes based on habit and experience; such disorder is an

inevitable feature of childhood. But what is not inevitable is that

our early experience will be rich enough to provide an adequate basis

for worthwhile ethical reflection; that is why we need to have been

brought up well. Yet such an upbringing can take us only so far. We

seek a deeper understanding of the objects of our childhood

enthusiasms, and we must systematize our goals so that as adults we

have a coherent plan of life. We need to engage in ethical theory, and

to reason well in this field, if we are to move beyond the low-grade

form of virtue we acquired as children.

3.2 Differences from and Affinities to Plato

Read in this way, Aristotle is engaged in a project similar in some

respects to the one Plato carried out in the Republic. One of

Plato’s central points is that it is a great advantage to

establish a hierarchical ordering of the elements in one’s soul;

and he shows how the traditional virtues can be interpreted to foster

or express the proper relation between reason and less rational

elements of the psyche. Aristotle’s approach is similar: his

“function argument” shows in a general way that our good

lies in the dominance of reason, and the detailed studies of the

particular virtues reveal how each of them involves the right kind of

ordering of the soul. Aristotle’s goal is to arrive at

conclusions like Plato’s, but without relying on the Platonic

metaphysics that plays a central role in the argument of the

Republic. He rejects the existence of Plato’s forms in

general and the form of the good in particular; and he rejects the

idea that in order to become fully virtuous one must study mathematics

and the sciences, and see all branches of knowledge as a unified

whole. Even though Aristotle’s ethical theory sometimes relies

on philosophical distinctions that are more fully developed in his

other works, he never proposes that students of ethics need to engage

in a specialized study of the natural world, or mathematics, or

eternal and changing objects. His project is to make ethics an

autonomous field, and to show why a full understanding of what is good

does not require expertise in any other field.

There is another contrast with Plato that should be emphasized: In

Book II of the Republic, we are told that the best type of

good is one that is desirable both in itself and for the sake of its

results (357d–358a). Plato argues that justice should be placed in

this category, but since it is generally agreed that it is desirable

for its consequences, he devotes most of his time to establishing his

more controversial point—that justice is to be sought for its

own sake. By contrast, Aristotle assumes that if A is

desirable for the sake of B, then B is better than

A (1094a14–16); therefore, the highest kind of good

must be one that is not desirable for the sake of anything else. To

show that A deserves to be our ultimate end, one must show

that all other goods are best thought of as instruments that promote

A in some way or other. Accordingly, it would not serve

Aristotle’s purpose to consider virtuous activity in isolation

from all other goods. He needs to discuss honor, wealth, pleasure, and

friendship in order to show how these goods, properly understood, can

be seen as resources that serve the higher goal of virtuous activity.

He vindicates the centrality of virtue in a well-lived life by showing

that in the normal course of things a virtuous person will not live a

life devoid of friends, honor, wealth, pleasure, and the like.

Virtuous activity makes a life happy not by guaranteeing happiness in

all circumstances, but by serving as the goal for the sake of which

lesser goods are to be pursued. Aristotle’s methodology in

ethics therefore pays more attention than does Plato’s to the

connections that normally obtain between virtue and other goods. That

is why he stresses that in this sort of study one must be satisfied

with conclusions that hold only for the most part (1094b11–22).

Poverty, isolation, and dishonor are normally impediments to the

exercise of virtue and therefore to happiness, although there may be

special circumstances in which they are not. The possibility of

exceptions does not undermine the point that, as a rule, to live well

is to have sufficient resources for the pursuit of virtue over the

course of a lifetime.

4. Virtues and Deficiencies, Continence and Incontinence

Aristotle distinguishes two kinds of virtue (1103a1–10): those

that pertain to the part of the soul that engages in reasoning

(virtues of mind or intellect), and those that pertain to the part of

the soul that cannot itself reason but is nonetheless capable of

following reason (ethical virtues, virtues of character). Intellectual

virtues are in turn divided into two sorts: those that pertain to

theoretical reasoning, and those that pertain to practical thinking

(1139a3–8). He organizes his material by first studying ethical

virtue in general, then moving to a discussion of particular ethical

virtues (temperance, courage, and so on), and finally completing his

survey by considering the intellectual virtues (practical wisdom,

theoretical wisdom, etc.).

All free males are born with the potential to become ethically

virtuous and practically wise, but to achieve these goals they must go

through two stages: during their childhood, they must develop the

proper habits; and then, when their reason is fully developed, they

must acquire practical wisdom (phronêsis). This does

not mean that first we fully acquire the ethical virtues, and then, at

a later stage, add on practical wisdom. Ethical virtue is fully

developed only when it is combined with practical wisdom

(1144b14–17). A low-grade form of ethical virtue emerges in us

during childhood as we are repeatedly placed in situations that call

for appropriate actions and emotions; but as we rely less on others

and become capable of doing more of our own thinking, we learn to

develop a larger picture of human life, our deliberative skills

improve, and our emotional responses are perfected. Like anyone who

has developed a skill in performing a complex and difficult activity,

the virtuous person takes pleasure in exercising his intellectual

skills. Furthermore, when he has decided what to do, he does not have

to contend with internal pressures to act otherwise. He does not long

to do something that he regards as shameful; and he is not greatly

distressed at having to give up a pleasure that he realizes he should

forego.

Aristotle places those who suffer from such internal disorders into

one of three categories: (A) Some agents, having reached a decision

about what to do on a particular occasion, experience some

counter-pressure brought on by an appetite for pleasure, or anger, or

some other emotion; and this countervailing influence is not

completely under the control of reason. (1) Within this category, some

are typically better able to resist these counter-rational pressures

than is the average person. Such people are not virtuous, although

they generally do what a virtuous person does. Aristotle calls them

“continent” (enkratês). But (2) others are

less successful than the average person in resisting these

counter-pressures. They are “incontinent”

(akratês). (The explanation of akrasia is a

topic to which we will return in section 7.) In addition, (B) there is

a type of agent who refuses even to try to do what an ethically

virtuous agent would do, because he has become convinced that justice,

temperance, generosity and the like are of little or no value. Such

people Aristotle calls evil (kakos, phaulos). He

assumes that evil people are driven by desires for domination and

luxury, and although they are single-minded in their pursuit of these

goals, he portrays them as deeply divided, because their

pleonexia—their desire for more and more—leaves

them dissatisfied and full of self-hatred.

It should be noticed that all three of these

deficiencies—continence, incontinence, vice—involve some

lack of internal harmony. (Here Aristotle’s debt to Plato is

particularly evident, for one of the central ideas of the

Republic is that the life of a good person is harmonious, and

all other lives deviate to some degree from this ideal.) The evil

person may wholeheartedly endorse some evil plan of action at a

particular moment, but over the course of time, Aristotle supposes, he

will regret his decision, because whatever he does will prove

inadequate for the achievement of his goals (1166b5–29).

Aristotle assumes that when someone systematically makes bad decisions

about how to live his life, his failures are caused by psychological

forces that are less than fully rational. His desires for pleasure,

power or some other external goal have become so strong that they make

him care too little or not at all about acting ethically. To keep such

destructive inner forces at bay, we need to develop the proper habits

and emotional responses when we are children, and to reflect

intelligently on our aims when we are adults. But some vulnerability

to these disruptive forces is present even in more-or-less virtuous

people; that is why even a good political community needs laws and the

threat of punishment. Clear thinking about the best goals of human

life and the proper way to put them into practice is a rare

achievement, because the human psyche is not a hospitable environment

for the development of these insights.

5. The Doctrine of the Mean

5.1 Ethical Virtue as Disposition

Aristotle describes ethical virtue as a “hexis”

(“state” “condition”

“disposition”)—a tendency or disposition, induced by

our habits, to have appropriate feelings (1105b25–6). Defective

states of character are hexeis (plural of hexis) as

well, but they are tendencies to have inappropriate feelings. The

significance of Aristotle’s characterization of these states as

hexeis is his decisive rejection of the thesis, found

throughout Plato’s early dialogues, that virtue is nothing but a

kind of knowledge and vice nothing but a lack of knowledge. Although

Aristotle frequently draws analogies between the crafts and the

virtues (and similarly between physical health and

eudaimonia), he insists that the virtues differ from the

crafts and all branches of knowledge in that the former involve

appropriate emotional responses and are not purely intellectual

conditions.

Furthermore, every ethical virtue is a condition intermediate (a

“golden mean” as it is popularly known) between two other

states, one involving excess, and the other deficiency

(1106a26–b28). In this respect, Aristotle says, the virtues are

no different from technical skills: every skilled worker knows how to

avoid excess and deficiency, and is in a condition intermediate

between two extremes. The courageous person, for example, judges that

some dangers are worth facing and others not, and experiences fear to

a degree that is appropriate to his circumstances. He lies between the

coward, who flees every danger and experiences excessive fear, and the

rash person, who judges every danger worth facing and experiences

little or no fear. Aristotle holds that this same topography applies

to every ethical virtue: all are located on a map that places the

virtues between states of excess and deficiency. He is careful to add,

however, that the mean is to be determined in a way that takes into

account the particular circumstances of the individual

(1106a36–b7). The arithmetic mean between 10 and 2 is 6, and

this is so invariably, whatever is being counted. But the intermediate

point that is chosen by an expert in any of the crafts will vary from

one situation to another. There is no universal rule, for example,

about how much food an athlete should eat, and it would be absurd to

infer from the fact that 10 lbs. is too much and 2 lbs. too little for

me that I should eat 6 lbs. Finding the mean in any given situation is

not a mechanical or thoughtless procedure, but requires a full and

detailed acquaintance with the circumstances.

It should be evident that Aristotle’s treatment of virtues as

mean states endorses the idea that we should sometimes have strong

feelings—when such feelings are called for by our situation.

Sometimes only a small degree of anger is appropriate; but at other

times, circumstances call for great anger. The right amount is not

some quantity between zero and the highest possible level, but rather

the amount, whatever it happens to be, that is proportionate to the

seriousness of the situation. Of course, Aristotle is committed to

saying that anger should never reach the point at which it undermines

reason; and this means that our passion should always fall short of

the extreme point at which we would lose control. But it is possible

to be very angry without going to this extreme, and Aristotle does not

intend to deny this.

The theory of the mean is open to several objections, but before

considering them, we should recognize that in fact there are two

distinct theses each of which might be called a doctrine of the mean.

First, there is the thesis that every virtue is a state that lies

between two vices, one of excess and the other of deficiency. Second,

there is the idea that whenever a virtuous person chooses to perform a

virtuous act, he can be described as aiming at an act that is in some

way or other intermediate between alternatives that he rejects. It is

this second thesis that is most likely to be found objectionable. A

critic might concede that in some cases virtuous acts can be described

in Aristotle’s terms. If, for example, one is trying to decide

how much to spend on a wedding present, one is looking for an amount

that is neither excessive nor deficient. But surely many other

problems that confront a virtuous agent are not susceptible to this

quantitative analysis. If one must decide whether to attend a wedding

or respect a competing obligation instead, it would not be

illuminating to describe this as a search for a mean between

extremes—unless “aiming at the mean” simply becomes

another phrase for trying to make the right decision. The objection,

then, is that Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean, taken as a

doctrine about what the ethical agent does when he deliberates, is in

many cases inapplicable or unilluminating.

A defense of Aristotle would have to say that the virtuous person does

after all aim at a mean, if we allow for a broad enough notion of what

sort of aiming is involved. For example, consider a juror who must

determine whether a defendant is guilty as charged. He does not have

before his mind a quantitative question; he is trying to decide

whether the accused committed the crime, and is not looking for some

quantity of action intermediate between extremes. Nonetheless, an

excellent juror can be described as someone who, in trying to arrive

at the correct decision, seeks to express the right degree of concern

for all relevant considerations. He searches for the verdict that

results from a deliberative process that is neither overly credulous

nor unduly skeptical. Similarly, in facing situations that arouse

anger, a virtuous agent must determine what action (if any) to take in

response to an insult, and although this is not itself a quantitative

question, his attempt to answer it properly requires him to have the

right degree of concern for his standing as a member of the community.

He aims at a mean in the sense that he looks for a response that

avoids too much or too little attention to factors that must be taken

into account in making a wise decision.

Perhaps a greater difficulty can be raised if we ask how Aristotle

determines which emotions are governed by the doctrine of the mean.

Consider someone who loves to wrestle, for example. Is this passion

something that must be felt by every human being at appropriate times

and to the right degree? Surely someone who never felt this emotion to

any degree could still live a perfectly happy life. Why then should we

not say the same about at least some of the emotions that Aristotle

builds into his analysis of the ethically virtuous agent? Why should

we experience anger at all, or fear, or the degree of concern for

wealth and honor that Aristotle commends? These are precisely the

questions that were asked in antiquity by the Stoics, and they came to

the conclusion that such common emotions as anger and fear are always

inappropriate. Aristotle assumes, on the contrary, not simply that

these common passions are sometimes appropriate, but that it is

essential that every human being learn how to master them and

experience them in the right way at the right times. A defense of his

position would have to show that the emotions that figure in his

account of the virtues are valuable components of any well-lived human

life, when they are experienced properly. Perhaps such a project could

be carried out, but Aristotle himself does not attempt to do so.

He often says, in the course of his discussion, that when the good

person chooses to act virtuously, he does so for the sake of the

“kalon”—a word that can mean

“beautiful”, “noble”, or “fine”

(see for example 1120a23–4). This term indicates that Aristotle

sees in ethical activity an attraction that is comparable to the

beauty of well-crafted artifacts, including such artifacts as poetry,

music, and drama. He draws this analogy in his discussion of the mean,

when he says that every craft tries to produce a work from which

nothing should be taken away and to which nothing further should be

added (1106b5–14). A craft product, when well designed and

produced by a good craftsman, is not merely useful, but also has such

elements as balance, proportion and harmony—for these are

properties that help make it useful. Similarly, Aristotle holds that a

well-executed project that expresses the ethical virtues will not

merely be advantageous but kalon as well—for the

balance it strikes is part of what makes it advantageous. The young

person learning to acquire the virtues must develop a love of doing

what is kalon and a strong aversion to its opposite—the

aischron, the shameful and ugly. Determining what is

kalon is difficult (1106b28–33, 1109a24–30), and

the normal human aversion to embracing difficulties helps account for

the scarcity of virtue (1104b10–11).

5.2 Ethical Theory Does Not Offer a Decision Procedure

It should be clear that neither the thesis that virtues lie between

extremes nor the thesis that the good person aims at what is

intermediate is intended as a procedure for making decisions. These

doctrines of the mean help show what is attractive about the virtues,

and they also help systematize our understanding of which qualities

are virtues. Once we see that temperance, courage, and other generally

recognized characteristics are mean states, we are in a position to

generalize and to identify other mean states as virtues, even though

they are not qualities for which we have a name. Aristotle remarks,

for example, that the mean state with respect to anger has no name in

Greek (1125b26–7). Though he is guided to some degree by

distinctions captured by ordinary terms, his methodology allows him to

recognize states for which no names exist.

So far from offering a decision procedure, Aristotle insists that this

is something that no ethical theory can do. His theory elucidates the

nature of virtue, but what must be done on any particular occasion by

a virtuous agent depends on the circumstances, and these vary so much

from one occasion to another that there is no possibility of stating a

series of rules, however complicated, that collectively solve every

practical problem. This feature of ethical theory is not unique;

Aristotle thinks it applies to many crafts, such as medicine and

navigation (1104a7–10). He says that the virtuous person

“sees the truth in each case, being as it were a standard and

measure of them” (1113a32–3); but this appeal to the good

person’s vision should not be taken to mean that he has an

inarticulate and incommunicable insight into the truth. Aristotle

thinks of the good person as someone who is good at deliberation, and

he describes deliberation as a process of rational inquiry. The

intermediate point that the good person tries to find is

determined by logos (“reason”,

“account”) and in the way that the person of practical

reason would determine it. (1107a1–2)

To say that such a person “sees” what to do is simply a

way of registering the point that the good person’s reasoning

does succeed in discovering what is best in each situation. He is

“as it were a standard and measure” in the sense that his

views should be regarded as authoritative by other members of the

community. A standard or measure is something that settles disputes;

and because good people are so skilled at discovering the mean in

difficult cases, their advice must be sought and heeded.

Although there is no possibility of writing a book of rules, however

long, that will serve as a complete guide to wise decision-making, it

would be a mistake to attribute to Aristotle the opposite position,

namely that every purported rule admits of exceptions, so that even a

small rule-book that applies to a limited number of situations is an

impossibility. He makes it clear that certain emotions (spite,

shamelessness, envy) and actions (adultery, theft, murder) are always

wrong, regardless of the circumstances (1107a8–12). Although he

says that the names of these emotions and actions convey their

wrongness, he should not be taken to mean that their wrongness derives

from linguistic usage. He defends the family as a social institution

against the criticisms of Plato (Politics II.3–4), and

so when he says that adultery is always wrong, he is prepared to argue

for his point by explaining why marriage is a valuable custom and why

extra-marital intercourse undermines the relationship between husband

and wife. He is not making the tautological claim that wrongful sexual

activity is wrong, but the more specific and contentious point that

marriages ought to be governed by a rule of strict fidelity.

Similarly, when he says that murder and theft are always wrong, he

does not mean that wrongful killing and taking are wrong, but that the

current system of laws regarding these matters ought to be strictly

enforced. So, although Aristotle holds that ethics cannot be reduced

to a system of rules, however complex, he insists that some rules are

inviolable.

5.3 The Starting Point for Practical Reasoning

We have seen that the decisions of a practically wise person are not

mere intuitions, but can be justified by a chain of reasoning. (This

is why Aristotle often talks in term of a practical syllogism, with a

major premise that identifies some good to be achieved, and a minor

premise that locates the good in some present-to-hand situation.) At

the same time, he is acutely aware of the fact that reasoning can

always be traced back to a starting point that is not itself justified

by further reasoning. Neither good theoretical reasoning nor good

practical reasoning moves in a circle; true thinking always

presupposes and progresses in linear fashion from proper starting

points. And that leads him to ask for an account of how the proper

starting points of reasoning are to be determined. Practical reasoning

always presupposes that one has some end, some goal one is trying to

achieve; and the task of reasoning is to determine how that goal is to

be accomplished. (This need not be means-end reasoning in the

conventional sense; if, for example, our goal is the just resolution

of a conflict, we must determine what constitutes justice in these

particular circumstances. Here we are engaged in ethical inquiry, and

are not asking a purely instrumental question.) But if practical

reasoning is correct only if it begins from a correct premise, what is

it that insures the correctness of its starting point?

Aristotle replies: “Virtue makes the goal right, practical

wisdom the things leading to it” (1144a7–8). By this he

cannot mean that there is no room for reasoning about our ultimate

end. For as we have seen, he gives a reasoned defense of his

conception of happiness as virtuous activity. What he must have in

mind, when he says that virtue makes the goal right, is that

deliberation typically proceeds from a goal that is far more specific

than the goal of attaining happiness by acting virtuously. To be sure,

there may be occasions when a good person approaches an ethical

problem by beginning with the premise that happiness consists in

virtuous activity. But more often what happens is that a concrete goal

presents itself as his starting point—helping a friend in need,

or supporting a worthwhile civic project. Which specific project we

set for ourselves is determined by our character. A good person starts

from worthwhile concrete ends because his habits and emotional

orientation have given him the ability to recognize that such goals

are within reach, here and now. Those who are defective in character

may have the rational skill needed to achieve their ends—the

skill Aristotle calls cleverness (1144a23–8)—but often the

ends they seek are worthless. The cause of this deficiency lies not in

some impairment in their capacity to reason—for we are assuming

that they are normal in this respect—but in the training of

their passions.

6. Intellectual Virtues

Since Aristotle often calls attention to the imprecision of ethical

theory (see e.g. 1104a1–7), it comes as a surprise to many

readers of the Ethics that he begins Book VI with the

admission that his earlier statements about the mean need

supplementation because they are not yet clear (saphes). In

every practical discipline, the expert aims at a mark and uses right

reason to avoid the twin extremes of excess and deficiency. But what

is this right reason, and by what standard (horos) is it to

be determined? Aristotle says that unless we answer that question, we

will be none the wiser—just as a student of medicine will have

failed to master his subject if he can only say that the right

medicines to administer are the ones that are prescribed by medical

expertise, but has no standard other than this (1138b18–34).

It is not easy to understand the point Aristotle is making here. Has

he not already told us that there can be no complete theoretical guide

to ethics, that the best one can hope for is that in particular

situations one’s ethical habits and practical wisdom will help

one determine what to do? Furthermore, Aristotle nowhere announces, in

the remainder of Book VI, that we have achieved the greater degree of

accuracy that he seems to be looking for. The rest of this Book is a

discussion of the various kinds of intellectual virtues: theoretical

wisdom, science (epistêmê), intuitive

understanding (nous), practical wisdom, and craft expertise.

Aristotle explains what each of these states of mind is, draws various

contrasts among them, and takes up various questions that can be

raised about their usefulness. At no point does he explicitly return

to the question he raised at the beginning of Book VI; he never says,

“and now we have the standard of right reason that we were

looking for”. Nor is it easy to see how his discussion of these

five intellectual virtues can bring greater precision to the doctrine

of the mean.

We can make some progress towards solving this problem if we remind

ourselves that at the beginning of the Ethics, Aristotle

describes his inquiry as an attempt to develop a better understanding

of what our ultimate aim should be. The sketchy answer he gives in

Book I is that happiness consists in virtuous activity. In Books II

through V, he describes the virtues of the part of the soul that is

rational in that it can be attentive to reason, even though it is not

capable of deliberating. But precisely because these virtues are

rational only in this derivative way, they are a less important

component of our ultimate end than is the intellectual

virtue—practical wisdom—with which they are integrated. If

what we know about virtue is only what is said in Books II through V,

then our grasp of our ultimate end is radically incomplete, because we

still have not studied the intellectual virtue that enables us to

reason well in any given situation. One of the things, at least,

towards which Aristotle is gesturing, as he begins Book VI, is

practical wisdom. This state of mind has not yet been analyzed, and

that is one reason why he complains that his account of our ultimate

end is not yet clear enough.

But is practical wisdom the only ingredient of our ultimate end that

has not yet been sufficiently discussed? Book VI discusses five

intellectual virtues, not just practical wisdom, but it is clear that

at least one of these—craft knowledge—is considered only

in order to provide a contrast with the others. Aristotle is not

recommending that his readers make this intellectual virtue part of

their ultimate aim. But what of the remaining three: science,

intuitive understanding, and the virtue that combines them,

theoretical wisdom? Are these present in Book VI only in order to

provide a contrast with practical wisdom, or is Aristotle saying that

these too must be components of our goal? He does not fully address

this issue, but it is evident from several of his remarks in Book VI

that he takes theoretical wisdom to be a more valuable state of mind

than practical wisdom.

It is strange if someone thinks that politics or practical wisdom is

the most excellent kind of knowledge, unless man is the best thing in

the cosmos. (1141a20–22)

He says that theoretical wisdom produces happiness by being a part of

virtue (1144a3–6), and that practical wisdom looks to the

development of theoretical wisdom, and issues commands for its sake

(1145a8–11). So it is clear that exercising theoretical wisdom

is a more important component of our ultimate goal than practical

wisdom.

Even so, it may still seem perplexing that these two intellectual

virtues, either separately or collectively, should somehow fill a gap

in the doctrine of the mean. Having read Book VI and completed our

study of what these two forms of wisdom are, how are we better able to

succeed in finding the mean in particular situations?

The answer to this question may be that Aristotle does not intend Book

VI to provide a full answer to that question, but rather to serve as a

prolegomenon to an answer. For it is only near the end of Book X that

he presents a full discussion of the relative merits of these two

kinds of intellectual virtue, and comments on the different degrees to

which each needs to be provided with resources. In X.7–8, he

argues that the happiest kind of life is that of a

philosopher—someone who exercises, over a long period of time,

the virtue of theoretical wisdom, and has sufficient resources for

doing so. (We will discuss these chapters more fully in section 10

below.) One of his reasons for thinking that such a life is superior

to the second-best kind of life—that of a political leader,

someone who devotes himself to the exercise of practical rather than

theoretical wisdom—is that it requires less external equipment

(1178a23–b7). Aristotle has already made it clear in his

discussion of the ethical virtues that someone who is greatly honored

by his community and commands large financial resources is in a

position to exercise a higher order of ethical virtue than is someone

who receives few honors and has little property. The virtue of

magnificence is superior to mere liberality, and similarly greatness

of soul is a higher excellence than the ordinary virtue that has to do

with honor. (These qualities are discussed in IV.1–4.) The

grandest expression of ethical virtue requires great political power,

because it is the political leader who is in a position to do the

greatest amount of good for the community. The person who chooses to

lead a political life, and who aims at the fullest expression of

practical wisdom, has a standard for deciding what level of resources

he needs: he should have friends, property, and honors in sufficient

quantities to allow his practical wisdom to express itself without

impediment. But if one chooses instead the life of a philosopher, then

one will look to a different standard—the fullest expression of

theoretical wisdom—and one will need a smaller supply of these

resources.

This enables us to see how Aristotle’s treatment of the

intellectual virtues does give greater content and precision to the

doctrine of the mean. The best standard is the one adopted by the

philosopher; the second-best is the one adopted by the political

leader. In either case, it is the exercise of an intellectual virtue

that provides a guideline for making important quantitative decisions.

This supplement to the doctrine of the mean is fully compatible with

Aristotle’s thesis that no set of rules, no matter how long and

detailed, obviates the need for deliberative and ethical virtue. If

one chooses the life of a philosopher, one should keep the level of

one’s resources high enough to secure the leisure necessary for

such a life, but not so high that one’s external equipment

becomes a burden and a distraction rather than an aid to living well.

That gives one a firmer idea of how to hit the mean, but it still

leaves the details to be worked out. The philosopher will need to

determine, in particular situations, where justice lies, how to spend

wisely, when to meet or avoid a danger, and so on. All of the normal

difficulties of ethical life remain, and they can be solved only by

means of a detailed understanding of the particulars of each

situation. Having philosophy as one’s ultimate aim does not put

an end to the need for developing and exercising practical wisdom and

the ethical virtues.

7. Akrasia

In VII.1–10 Aristotle investigates character

traits—continence and incontinence—that are not as

blameworthy as the vices but not as praiseworthy as the virtues. (We

began our discussion of these qualities in section 4.) The Greek terms

are akrasia (“incontinence”; literally:

“lack of mastery”) and enkrateia

(“continence”; literally “mastery”). An

akratic person goes against reason as a result of some pathos

(“emotion”, “feeling”). Like the akratic, an

enkratic person experiences a feeling that is contrary to reason; but

unlike the akratic, he acts in accordance with reason. His defect

consists solely in the fact that, more than most people, he

experiences passions that conflict with his rational choice. The

akratic person has not only this defect, but has the further flaw that

he gives in to feeling rather than reason more often than the average

person.

Aristotle distinguishes two kinds of akrasia: impetuosity

(propeteia) and weakness (astheneia). The person who

is weak goes through a process of deliberation and makes a choice; but

rather than act in accordance with his reasoned choice, he acts under

the influence of a passion. By contrast, the impetuous person does not

go through a process of deliberation and does not make a reasoned

choice; he simply acts under the influence of a passion. At the time

of action, the impetuous person experiences no internal conflict. But

once his act has been completed, he regrets what he has done. One

could say that he deliberates, if deliberation were something that

post-dated rather than preceded action; but the thought process he

goes through after he acts comes too late to save him from error.

It is important to bear in mind that when Aristotle talks about

impetuosity and weakness, he is discussing chronic conditions. The

impetuous person is someone who acts emotionally and fails to

deliberate not just once or twice but with some frequency; he makes

this error more than most people do. Because of this pattern in his

actions, we would be justified in saying of the impetuous person that

had his passions not prevented him from doing so, he would have

deliberated and chosen an action different from the one he did

perform.

The two kinds of passions that Aristotle focuses on, in his treatment

of akrasia, are the appetite for pleasure and anger. Either

can lead to impetuosity and weakness. But Aristotle gives pride of

place to the appetite for pleasure as the passion that undermines

reason. He calls the kind of akrasia caused by an appetite

for pleasure “unqualified akrasia”—or, as

we might say, akrasia “full stop”;

akrasia caused by anger he considers a qualified form of

akrasia and calls it akrasia “with respect to

anger”. We thus have these four forms of akrasia: (A)

impetuosity caused by pleasure, (B) impetuosity caused by anger, (C)

weakness caused by pleasure (D) weakness caused by anger. It should be

noticed that Aristotle’s treatment of akrasia is

heavily influenced by Plato’s tripartite division of the soul in

the Republic. Plato holds that either the spirited part

(which houses anger, as well as other emotions) or the appetitive part

(which houses the desire for physical pleasures) can disrupt the

dictates of reason and result in action contrary to reason. The same

threefold division of the soul can be seen in Aristotle’s

approach to this topic.

Although Aristotle characterizes akrasia and

enkrateia in terms of a conflict between reason and feeling,

his detailed analysis of these states of mind shows that what takes

place is best described in a more complicated way. For the feeling

that undermines reason contains some thought, which may be implicitly

general. As Aristotle says, anger “reasoning as it were that one

must fight against such a thing, is immediately provoked”

(1149a33–4). And although in the next sentence he denies that

our appetite for pleasure works in this way, he earlier had said that

there can be a syllogism that favors pursuing enjoyment:

“Everything sweet is pleasant, and this is sweet” leads to

the pursuit of a particular pleasure (1147a31–30). Perhaps what

he has in mind is that pleasure can operate in either way: it can

prompt action unmediated by a general premise, or it can prompt us to

act on such a syllogism. By contrast, anger always moves us by

presenting itself as a bit of general, although hasty, reasoning.

But of course Aristotle does not mean that a conflicted person has

more than one faculty of reason. Rather his idea seems to be that in

addition to our full-fledged reasoning capacity, we also have

psychological mechanisms that are capable of a limited range of

reasoning. When feeling conflicts with reason, what occurs is better

described as a fight between feeling-allied-with-limited-reasoning and

full-fledged reason. Part of us—reason—can remove itself

from the distorting influence of feeling and consider all relevant

factors, positive and negative. But another part of us—feeling

or emotion—has a more limited field of reasoning—and

sometimes it does not even make use of it.

Although “passion” is sometimes used as a translation of

Aristotle’s word pathos (other alternatives are

“emotion” and “feeling”), it is important to

bear in mind that his term does not necessarily designate a strong

psychological force. Anger is a pathos whether it is weak or

strong; so too is the appetite for bodily pleasures. And he clearly

indicates that it is possible for an akratic person to be defeated by

a weak pathos—the kind that most people would easily be

able to control (1150a9–b16). So the general explanation for the

occurrence of akrasia cannot be that the strength of a

passion overwhelms reason. Aristotle should therefore be acquitted of

an accusation made against him by J.L. Austin in a well-known footnote

to his paper, “A Plea For Excuses”. Plato and Aristotle,

he says, collapsed all succumbing to temptation into losing control of

ourselves—a mistake illustrated by this example:

I am very partial to ice cream, and a bombe is served divided into

segments corresponding one to one with the persons at High Table: I am

tempted to help myself to two segments and do so, thus succumbing to

temptation and even conceivably (but why necessarily?) going against

my principles. But do I lose control of myself? Do I raven, do I

snatch the morsels from the dish and wolf them down, impervious to the

consternation of my colleagues? Not a bit of it. We often succumb to

temptation with calm and even with finesse. (1957: 24, fn 13 [1961:

146])

With this, Aristotle can agree: the pathos for the bombe can

be a weak one, and in some people that will be enough to get them to

act in a way that is disapproved by their reason at the very time of

action.

What is most remarkable about Aristotle’s discussion of

akrasia is that he defends a position close to that of

Socrates. When he first introduces the topic of akrasia, and

surveys some of the problems involved in understanding this

phenomenon, he says (1145b25–8) that Socrates held that there is

no akrasia, and he describes this as a thesis that clearly

conflicts with the appearances (phainomena). Since he says

that his goal is to preserve as many of the appearances as possible

(1145b2–7), it may come as a surprise that when he analyzes the

conflict between reason and feeling, he arrives at the conclusion that

in a way Socrates was right after all (1147b13–17). For, he

says, the person who acts against reason does not have what is thought

to be unqualified knowledge; in a way he has knowledge, but in a way

does not.

Aristotle explains what he has in mind by comparing akrasia

to the condition of other people who might be described as knowing in

a way, but not in an unqualified way. His examples are people who are

asleep, mad, or drunk; he also compares the akratic to a student who

has just begun to learn a subject, or an actor on the stage

(1147a10–24). All of these people, he says, can utter the very

words used by those who have knowledge; but their talk does not prove

that they really have knowledge, strictly speaking.

These analogies can be taken to mean that the form of akrasia

that Aristotle calls weakness rather than impetuosity always results

from some diminution of cognitive or intellectual acuity at the moment

of action. The akratic says, at the time of action, that he ought not

to indulge in this particular pleasure at this time. But does he know

or even believe that he should refrain? Aristotle might be taken to

reply: yes and no. He has some degree of recognition that he must not

do this now, but not full recognition. His feeling, even if it is

weak, has to some degree prevented him from completely grasping or

affirming the point that he should not do this. And so in a way

Socrates was right. When reason remains unimpaired and unclouded, its

dictates will carry us all the way to action, so long as we are able

to act.

But Aristotle’s agreement with Socrates is only partial, because

he insists on the power of the emotions to rival, weaken or bypass

reason. Emotion challenges reason in all three of these ways. In both

the akratic and the enkratic, it competes with reason for control over

action; even when reason wins, it faces the difficult task of having

to struggle with an internal rival. Second, in the akratic, it

temporarily robs reason of its full acuity, thus handicapping it as a

competitor. It is not merely a rival force, in these cases; it is a

force that keeps reason from fully exercising its power. And third,

passion can make someone impetuous; here its victory over reason is so

powerful that the latter does not even enter into the arena of

conscious reflection until it is too late to influence action.

Supplementary Document: Alternate Readings of Aristotle on Akrasia

8. Pleasure

Aristotle frequently emphasizes the importance of pleasure to human

life and therefore to his study of how we should live (see for example

1099a7–20 and 1104b3–1105a16), but his full-scale

examination of the nature and value of pleasure is found in two

places: VII.11–14 and X.1–5. It is odd that pleasure

receives two lengthy treatments; no other topic in the Ethics

is revisited in this way. Book VII of the Nicomachean Ethics

is identical to Book VI of the Eudemian Ethics; for unknown

reasons, the editor of the former decided to include within it both

the treatment of pleasure that is unique to that work (X.1–5)

and the study that is common to both treatises (VII.11–14). The

two accounts are broadly similar. They agree about the value of

pleasure, defend a theory about its nature, and oppose competing

theories. Aristotle holds that a happy life must include pleasure, and

he therefore opposes those who argue that pleasure is by its nature

bad. He insists that there are other pleasures besides those of the

senses, and that the best pleasures are the ones experienced by

virtuous people who have sufficient resources for excellent

activity.

Book VII offers a brief account of what pleasure is and is not. It is

not a process but an unimpeded activity of a natural state

(1153a7–17). Aristotle does not elaborate on what a natural

state is, but he obviously has in mind the healthy condition of the

body, especially its sense faculties, and the virtuous condition of

the soul. Little is said about what it is for an activity to be

unimpeded, but Aristotle does remind us that virtuous activity is

impeded by the absence of a sufficient supply of external goods

(1153b17–19). One might object that people who are sick or who

have moral deficiencies can experience pleasure, even though Aristotle

does not take them to be in a natural state. He has two strategies for

responding. First, when a sick person experiences some degree of

pleasure as he is being restored to health, the pleasure he is feeling

is caused by the fact that he is no longer completely ill. Some small

part of him is in a natural state and is acting without impediment

(1152b35–6). Second, Aristotle is willing to say that what seems

pleasant to some people may in fact not be pleasant (1152b31–2),

just as what tastes bitter to an unhealthy palate may not be bitter.

To call something a pleasure is not only to report a state of mind but

also to endorse it to others. Aristotle’s analysis of the nature

of pleasure is not meant to apply to every case in which something

seems pleasant to someone, but only to activities that really are

pleasures. All of these are unimpeded activities of a natural

state.

It follows from this conception of pleasure that every instance of

pleasure must be good to some extent. For how could an unimpeded

activity of a natural state be bad or a matter of indifference? On the

other hand, Aristotle does not mean to imply that every pleasure

should be chosen. He briefly mentions the point that pleasures compete

with each other, so that the enjoyment of one kind of activity impedes

other activities that cannot be carried out at the same time

(1153a20–22). His point is simply that although some pleasures

may be good, they are not worth choosing when they interfere with

other activities that are far better. This point is developed more

fully in Ethics X.5.

Furthermore, Aristotle’s analysis allows him to speak of certain

pleasures as “bad without qualification”

(1152b26–33), even though pleasure is the unimpeded activity of

a natural state. To call a pleasure “bad without

qualification” is to insist that it should be avoided, but allow

that nonetheless it should be chosen in constraining circumstances.

The pleasure of recovering from an illness, for example, is bad

without qualification—meaning that it is not one of the

pleasures one would ideally choose, if one could completely control

one’s circumstances. Although it really is a pleasure and so

something can be said in its favor, it is so inferior to other goods

that ideally one ought to forego it. Nonetheless, it is a pleasure

worth having—if one adds the qualification that it is only worth

having in undesirable circumstances. The pleasure of recovering from

an illness is good, because some small part of oneself is in a natural

state and is acting without impediment; but it can also be called bad,

if what one means by this is that one should avoid getting into a

situation in which one experiences that pleasure.

Aristotle indicates several times in VII.11–14 that merely to

say that pleasure is a good does not do it enough justice; he

also wants to say that the highest good is a pleasure. Here he is

influenced by an idea expressed in the opening line of the

Ethics: the good is that at which all things aim. In VII.13,

he hints at the idea that all living things imitate the contemplative

activity of god (1153b31–2). Plants and non-human animals seek

to reproduce themselves because that is their way of participating in

an unending series, and this is the closest they can come to the

ceaseless thinking of the unmoved mover. Aristotle makes this point in

several of his works (see for example De Anima

415a23–b7), and in Ethics X.7–8 he gives a full

defense of the idea that the happiest human life resembles the life of

a divine being. He conceives of god as a being who continually enjoys

a “single and simple pleasure” (1154b26)—the

pleasure of pure thought—whereas human beings, because of their

complexity, grow weary of whatever they do. He will elaborate on these

points in X.8; in VII.11–14, he appeals to his conception of

divine activity only in order to defend the thesis that our highest

good consists in a certain kind of pleasure. Human happiness does not

consist in every kind of pleasure, but it does consist in one kind of

pleasure—the pleasure felt by a human being who engages in

theoretical activity and thereby imitates the pleasurable thinking of

god.

Book X offers a much more elaborate account of what pleasure is and

what it is not. It is not a process, because processes go through

developmental stages: building a temple is a process because the

temple is not present all at once, but only comes into being through

stages that unfold over time. By contrast, pleasure, like seeing and

many other activities, is not something that comes into existence

through a developmental process. If I am enjoying a conversation, for

example, I do not need to wait until it is finished in order to feel

pleased; I take pleasure in the activity all along the way. The

defining nature of pleasure is that it is an activity that accompanies

other activities, and in some sense brings them to completion.

Pleasure occurs when something within us, having been brought into

good condition, is activated in relation to an external object that is

also in good condition. The pleasure of drawing, for example, requires

both the development of drawing ability and an object of attention

that is worth drawing.

The conception of pleasure that Aristotle develops in Book X is

obviously closely related to the analysis he gives in Book VII. But

the theory proposed in the later Book brings out a point that had

received too little attention earlier: pleasure is by its nature

something that accompanies something else. It is not enough to say

that it is what happens when we are in good condition and are active

in unimpeded circumstances; one must add to that point the further

idea that pleasure plays a certain role in complementing something

other than itself. Drawing well and the pleasure of drawing well

always occur together, and so they are easy to confuse, but

Aristotle’s analysis in Book X emphasizes the importance of

making this distinction.

He says that pleasure completes the activity that it accompanies, but

then adds, mysteriously, that it completes the activity in the manner

of an end that is added on. In the translation of W.D. Ross, it

“supervenes as the bloom of youth does on those in the flower of

their age” (1174b33). It is unclear what thought is being

expressed here, but perhaps Aristotle is merely trying to avoid a

possible misunderstanding: when he says that pleasure completes an

activity, he does not mean that the activity it accompanies is in some

way defective, and that the pleasure improves the activity by removing

this defect. Aristotle’s language is open to that

misinterpretation because the verb that is translated

“complete” (teleein) can also mean

“perfect”. The latter might be taken to mean that the

activity accompanied by pleasure has not yet reached a sufficiently

high level of excellence, and that the role of pleasure is to bring it

to the point of perfection. Aristotle does not deny that when we take

pleasure in an activity we get better at it, but when he says that

pleasure completes an activity by supervening on it, like the bloom

that accompanies those who have achieved the highest point of physical

beauty, his point is that the activity complemented by pleasure is

already perfect, and the pleasure that accompanies it is a bonus that

serves no further purpose. Taking pleasure in an activity does help us

improve at it, but enjoyment does not cease when perfection is

achieved—on the contrary, that is when pleasure is at its peak.

That is when it reveals most fully what it is: an added bonus that

crowns our achievement.

It is clear, at any rate, that in Book X Aristotle gives a fuller

account of what pleasure is than he had in Book VII. We should take

note of a further difference between these two discussions: In Book X,

he makes the point that pleasure is a good but not

the good. He cites and endorses an argument given by Plato in

the Philebus: If we imagine a life filled with pleasure and

then mentally add wisdom to it, the result is made more desirable. But

the good is something that cannot be improved upon in this way.

Therefore pleasure is not the good (1172b23–35). By contrast, in

Book VII Aristotle strongly implies that the pleasure of contemplation

is the good, because in one way or another all living beings

aim at this sort of pleasure. Aristotle observes in Book X that what

all things aim at is good (1172b35–1173a1); significantly, he

falls short of endorsing the argument that since all aim at pleasure,

it must be the good.

Book VII makes the point that pleasures interfere with each other, and

so even if all kinds of pleasures are good, it does not follow that

all of them are worth choosing. One must make a selection among

pleasures by determining which are better. But how is one to make this

choice? Book VII does not say, but in Book X, Aristotle holds that the

selection of pleasures is not to be made with reference to pleasure

itself, but with reference to the activities they accompany.

Since activities differ with respect to goodness and badness, some

being worth choosing, others worth avoiding, and others neither, the

same is true of pleasures as well. (1175b24–6)

Aristotle’s statement implies that in order to determine whether

(for example) the pleasure of virtuous activity is more desirable than

that of eating, we are not to attend to the pleasures themselves but

to the activities with which we are pleased. A pleasure’s

goodness derives from the goodness of its associated activity. And

surely the reason why pleasure is not the criterion to which we should

look in making these decisions is that it is not the good. The

standard we should use in making comparisons between rival options is

virtuous activity, because that has been shown to be identical to

happiness.

That is why Aristotle says that what is judged pleasant by a good man

really is pleasant, because the good man is the measure of things

(1176a15–19). He does not mean that the way to lead our lives is

to search for a good man and continually rely on him to tell us what

is pleasurable. Rather, his point is that there is no way of telling

what is genuinely pleasurable (and therefore what is most pleasurable)

unless we already have some other standard of value. Aristotle’s

discussion of pleasure thus helps confirm his initial hypothesis that

to live our lives well we must focus on one sort of good above all

others: virtuous activity. It is the good in terms of which all other

goods must be understood. Aristotle’s analysis of friendship

supports the same conclusion.

9. Friendship

The topic of Books VIII and IX of the Ethics is friendship.

Although it is difficult to avoid the term “friendship” as

a translation of “philia”, and this is an

accurate term for the kind of relationship he is most interested in,

we should bear in mind that he is discussing a wider range of

phenomena than this translation might lead us to expect, for the

Greeks use the term, “philia”, to name the

relationship that holds among family members, and do not reserve it

for voluntary relationships. Although Aristotle is interested in

classifying the different forms that friendship takes, his main theme

in Books VIII and IX is to show the close relationship between

virtuous activity and friendship. He is vindicating his conception of

happiness as virtuous activity by showing how satisfying are the

relationships that a virtuous person can normally expect to have.

His taxonomy begins with the premise that there are three main reasons

why one person might like someone else. (The verb,

“philein”, which is cognate to the noun

“philia”, can sometimes be translated

“like” or even “love”—though in other

cases philia involves very little in the way of feeling.) One

might like someone because he is good, or because he is useful, or

because he is pleasant. And so there are three bases for friendships,

depending on which of these qualities binds friends together. When two

individuals recognize that the other person is someone of good

character, and they spend time with each other, engaged in activities

that exercise their virtues, then they form one kind of friendship. If

they are equally virtuous, their friendship is perfect. If, however,

there is a large gap in their moral development (as between a parent

and a small child, or between a husband and a wife), then although

their relationship may be based on the other person’s good

character, it will be imperfect precisely because of their

inequality.

The imperfect friendships that Aristotle focuses on, however, are not

unequal relationships based on good character. Rather, they are

relationships held together because each individual regards the other

as the source of some advantage to himself or some pleasure he

receives. When Aristotle calls these relationships

“imperfect”, he is tacitly relying on widely accepted

assumptions about what makes a relationship satisfying. These

friendships are defective, and have a smaller claim to be called

“friendships”, because the individuals involved have

little trust in each other, quarrel frequently, and are ready to break

off their association abruptly. Aristotle does not mean to suggest

that unequal relations based on the mutual recognition of good

character are defective in these same ways. Rather, when he says that

unequal relationships based on character are imperfect, his point is

that people are friends in the fullest sense when they gladly spend

their days together in shared activities, and this close and constant

interaction is less available to those who are not equal in their

moral development.

When Aristotle begins his discussion of friendship, he introduces a

notion that is central to his understanding of this phenomenon: a

genuine friend is someone who loves or likes another person for the

sake of that other person. Wanting what is good for the sake of

another he calls “good will” (eunoia), and

friendship is reciprocal good will, provided that each recognizes the

presence of this attitude in the other. Does such good will exist in

all three kinds of friendship, or is it confined to relationships

based on virtue? At first, Aristotle leaves open the first of these

two possibilities. He says:

it is necessary that friends bear good will to each other and wish

good things for each other, without this escaping their notice,

because of one of the reasons mentioned. (1156a4–5)

The reasons mentioned are goodness, pleasure, and advantage; and so it

seems that Aristotle is leaving room for the idea that in all three

kinds of friendships, even those based on advantage and pleasure

alone, the individuals wish each other well for the sake of the

other.

But in fact, as Aristotle continues to develop his taxonomy, he does

not choose to exploit this possibility. He speaks as though it is only

in friendships based on character that one finds a desire to benefit

the other person for the sake of the other person.

Those who wish good things to their friends for the sake of the latter

are friends most of all, because they do so because of their friends

themselves, and not coincidentally. (1156b9–11)

When one benefits someone not because of the kind of person he is, but

only because of the advantages to oneself, then, Aristotle says, one

is not a friend towards the other person, but only towards the profit

that comes one’s way (1157a15–16).

In such statements as these, Aristotle comes rather close to saying

that relationships based on profit or pleasure should not be called

friendships at all. But he decides to stay close to common parlance

and to use the term “friend” loosely. Friendships based on

character are the ones in which each person benefits the other for the

sake of other; and these are friendships most of all. Because each

party benefits the other, it is advantageous to form such friendships.

And since each enjoys the trust and companionship of the other, there

is considerable pleasure in these relationships as well. Because these

perfect friendships produce advantages and pleasures for each of the

parties, there is some basis for going along with common usage and

calling any relationship entered into for the sake of just one of

these goods a friendship. Friendships based on advantage alone or

pleasure alone deserve to be called friendships because in

full-fledged friendships these two properties, advantage and pleasure,

are present. It is striking that in the Ethics Aristotle

never thinks of saying that the uniting factor in all friendships is

the desire each friend has for the good of the other.

Aristotle does not raise questions about what it is to desire good for

the sake of another person. He treats this as an easily understood

phenomenon, and has no doubts about its existence. But it is also

clear that he takes this motive to be compatible with a love of

one’s own good and a desire for one’s own happiness.

Someone who has practical wisdom will recognize that he needs friends

and other resources in order to exercise his virtues over a long

period of time. When he makes friends, and benefits friends he has

made, he will be aware of the fact that such a relationship is good

for him. And yet to have a friend is to want to benefit someone for

that other person’s sake; it is not a merely self-interested

strategy. Aristotle sees no difficulty here, and rightly so. For there

is no reason why acts of friendship should not be undertaken partly

for the good of one’s friend and partly for one’s own

good. Acting for the sake of another does not in itself demand

self-sacrifice. It requires caring about someone other than oneself,

but does not demand some loss of care for oneself. For when we know

how to benefit a friend for his sake, we exercise the ethical virtues,

and this is precisely what our happiness consists in.

Aristotle makes it clear that the number of people with whom one can

sustain the kind of relationship he calls a perfect friendship is

quite small (IX.10). Even if one lived in a city populated entirely by

perfectly virtuous citizens, the number with whom one could carry on a

friendship of the perfect type would be at most a handful. For he

thinks that this kind of friendship can exist only when one spends a

great deal of time with the other person, participating in joint

activities and engaging in mutually beneficial behavior; and one

cannot cooperate on these close terms with every member of the

political community. One may well ask why this kind of close

friendship is necessary for happiness. If one lived in a community

filled with good people, and cooperated on an occasional basis with

each of them, in a spirit of good will and admiration, would that not

provide sufficient scope for virtuous activity and a well-lived life?

Admittedly, close friends are often in a better position to benefit

each other than are fellow citizens, who generally have little

knowledge of one’s individual circumstances. But this only shows

that it is advantageous to be on the receiving end of a friend’s

help. The more important question for Aristotle is why one needs to be

on the giving end of this relationship. And obviously the answer

cannot be that one needs to give in order to receive; that would turn

active love for one’s friend into a mere means to the benefits

received.

Aristotle attempts to answer this question in IX.11, but his treatment

is disappointing. His fullest argument depends crucially on the notion

that a friend is “another self”, someone, in other words,

with whom one has a relationship very similar to the relationship one

has with oneself. A virtuous person loves the recognition of himself

as virtuous; to have a close friend is to possess yet another person,

besides oneself, whose virtue one can recognize at extremely close

quarters; and so, it must be desirable to have someone very much like

oneself whose virtuous activity one can perceive. The argument is

unconvincing because it does not explain why the perception of

virtuous activity in fellow citizens would not be an adequate

substitute for the perception of virtue in one’s friends.

Aristotle would be on stronger grounds if he could show that in the

absence of close friends one would be severely restricted in the kinds

of virtuous activities one could undertake. But he cannot present such

an argument, because he does not believe it. He says that it is

“finer and more godlike” to bring about the well being of

a whole city than to sustain the happiness of just one person

(1094b7–10). He refuses to regard private life—the realm

of the household and the small circle of one’s friends—as

the best or most favorable location for the exercise of virtue. He is

convinced that the loss of this private sphere would greatly detract

from a well-lived life, but he is hard put to explain why. He might

have done better to focus on the benefits of being the object of a

close friend’s solicitude. Just as property is ill cared for

when it is owned by all, and just as a child would be poorly nurtured

were he to receive no special parental care—points Aristotle

makes in Politics II.2–5—so in the absence of

friendship we would lose a benefit that could not be replaced by the

care of the larger community. But Aristotle is not looking for a

defense of this sort, because he conceives of friendship as lying

primarily in activity rather than receptivity. It is difficult, within

his framework, to show that virtuous activity towards a friend is a

uniquely important good.

Since Aristotle thinks that the pursuit of one’s own happiness,

properly understood, requires ethically virtuous activity and will

therefore be of great value not only to one’s friends but to the

larger political community as well, he argues that self-love is an

entirely proper emotion—provided it is expressed in the love of

virtue (IX.8). Self-love is rightly condemned when it consists in the

pursuit of as large a share of external goods—particularly

wealth and power—as one can acquire, because such self-love

inevitably brings one into conflict with others and undermines the

stability of the political community. It may be tempting to cast

Aristotle’s defense of self-love into modern terms by calling

him an egoist, and “egoism” is a broad enough term so

that, properly defined, it can be made to fit Aristotle’s

ethical outlook. If egoism is the thesis that one will always act

rightly if one consults one’s self-interest, properly

understood, then nothing would be amiss in identifying him as an

egoist.

But egoism is sometimes understood in a stronger sense. Just as

consequentialism is the thesis that one should maximize the general

good, whatever the good turns out to be, so egoism can be defined as

the parallel thesis that one should maximize one’s own good,

whatever the good turns out to be. Egoism, in other words, can be

treated as a purely formal thesis: it holds that whether the good is

pleasure, or virtue, or the satisfaction of desires, one should not

attempt to maximize the total amount of good in the world, but only

one’s own. When egoism takes this abstract form, it is an

expression of the idea that the claims of others are never worth

attending to, unless in some way or other their good can be shown to

serve one’s own. The only underived reason for action is

self-interest; that an act helps another does not by itself provide a

reason for performing it, unless some connection can be made between

the good of that other and one’s own.

There is no reason to attribute this extreme form of egoism to

Aristotle. On the contrary, his defense of self-love makes it clear

that he is not willing to defend the bare idea that one ought to love

oneself alone or above others; he defends self-love only when this

emotion is tied to the correct theory of where one’s good lies,

for it is only in this way that he can show that self-love need not be

a destructive passion. He takes it for granted that self-love is

properly condemned whenever it can be shown to be harmful to the

community. It is praiseworthy only if it can be shown that a

self-lover will be an admirable citizen. In making this assumption,

Aristotle reveals that he thinks that the claims of other members of

the community to proper treatment are intrinsically valid. This is

precisely what a strong form of egoism cannot accept.

We should also keep in mind Aristotle’s statement in the

Politics that the political community is prior to the

individual citizen—just as the whole body is prior to any of its

parts (1253a18–29). Aristotle makes use of this claim when he

proposes that in the ideal community each child should receive the

same education, and that the responsibility for providing such an

education should be taken out of the hands of private individuals and

made a matter of common concern (1337a21–7). No citizen, he

says, belongs to himself; all belong to the city (1337a28–9).

What he means is that when it comes to such matters as education,

which affect the good of all, each individual should be guided by the

collective decisions of the whole community. An individual citizen

does not belong to himself, in the sense that it is not up to him

alone to determine how he should act; he should subordinate his

individual decision-making powers to those of the whole. The strong

form of egoism we have been discussing cannot accept Aristotle’s

doctrine of the priority of the city to the individual. It tells the

individual that the good of others has, in itself, no valid claim on

him, but that he should serve other members of the community only to

the extent that he can connect their interests to his own. Such a

doctrine leaves no room for the thought that the individual citizen

does not belong to himself but to the whole.

10. Three Lives Compared

In Book I Aristotle says that three kinds of lives are thought to be

especially attractive: one is devoted to pleasure, a second to

politics, and a third to knowledge and understanding

(1095b17–19). In X.6–9 he returns to these three

alternatives, and explores them more fully than he had in Book I. The

life of pleasure is construed in Book I as a life devoted to physical

pleasure, and is quickly dismissed because of its vulgarity. In X.6,

Aristotle concedes that physical pleasures, and more generally,

amusements of all sorts, are desirable in themselves, and therefore

have some claim to be our ultimate end. But his discussion of

happiness in Book X does not start from scratch; he builds on his

thesis that pleasure cannot be our ultimate target, because what

counts as pleasant must be judged by some standard other than pleasure

itself, namely the judgment of the virtuous person. Amusements will

not be absent from a happy life, since everyone needs relaxation, and

amusements fill this need. But they play a subordinate role, because

we seek relaxation in order to return to more important

activities.

Aristotle turns therefore, in X.7–8, to the two remaining

alternatives—politics and philosophy—and presents a series

of arguments to show that the philosophical life, a life devoted to

theoria (contemplation, study), is best. Theoria is

not the process of learning that leads to understanding; that process

is not a candidate for our ultimate end, because it is undertaken for

the sake of a further goal. What Aristotle has in mind when he talks

about theoria is the activity of someone who has already

achieved theoretical wisdom. The happiest life is lived by someone who

has a full understanding of the basic causal principles that govern

the operation of the universe, and who has the resources needed for

living a life devoted to the exercise of that understanding. Evidently

Aristotle believes that his own life and that of his philosophical

friends was the best available to a human being. He compares it to the

life of a god: god thinks without interruption and endlessly, and a

philosopher enjoys something similar for a limited period of time.

It may seem odd that after devoting so much attention to the practical

virtues, Aristotle should conclude his treatise with the thesis that

the best activity of the best life is not ethical. In fact, some

scholars have held that X.7–8 are deeply at odds with the rest

of the Ethics; they take Aristotle to be saying that we

should be prepared to act unethically, if need be, in order to devote

ourselves as much as possible to contemplation. But it is difficult to

believe that he intends to reverse himself so abruptly, and there are

many indications that he intends the arguments of X.7–8 to be

continuous with the themes he emphasizes throughout the rest of the

Ethics. The best way to understand him is to take him to be

assuming that one will need the ethical virtues in order to live the

life of a philosopher, even though exercising those virtues is not the

philosopher’s ultimate end. To be adequately equipped to live a

life of thought and discussion, one will need practical wisdom,

temperance, justice, and the other ethical virtues. To say that there

is something better even than ethical activity, and that ethical

activity promotes this higher goal, is entirely compatible with

everything else that we find in the Ethics.

Although Aristotle’s principal goal in X.7–8 is to show

the superiority of philosophy to politics, he does not deny that a

political life is happy. Perfect happiness, he says, consists in

contemplation; but he indicates that the life devoted to practical

thought and ethical virtue is happy in a secondary way. He thinks of

this second-best life as that of a political leader, because he

assumes that the person who most fully exercises such qualities as

justice and greatness of soul is the man who has the large resources

needed to promote the common good of the city. The political life has

a major defect, despite the fact that it consists in fully exercising

the ethical virtues, because it is a life devoid of philosophical

understanding and activity. Were someone to combine both careers,

practicing politics at certain times and engaged in philosophical

discussion at other times (as Plato’s philosopher-kings do), he

would lead a life better than that of Aristotle’s politician,

but worse than that of Aristotle’s philosopher.

But his complaint about the political life is not simply that it is

devoid of philosophical activity. The points he makes against it

reveal drawbacks inherent in ethical and political activity. Perhaps

the most telling of these defects is that the life of the political

leader is in a certain sense unleisurely (1177b4–15). What

Aristotle has in mind when he makes this complaint is that ethical

activities are remedial: they are needed when something has gone

wrong, or threatens to do so. Courage, for example, is exercised in

war, and war remedies an evil; it is not something we should wish for.

Aristotle implies that all other political activities have the same

feature, although perhaps to a smaller degree. Corrective justice

would provide him with further evidence for his thesis—but what

of justice in the distribution of goods? Perhaps Aristotle would reply

that in existing political communities a virtuous person must

accommodate himself to the least bad method of distribution, because,

human nature being what it is, a certain amount of injustice must be

tolerated. As the courageous person cannot be completely satisfied

with his courageous action, no matter how much self-mastery it shows,

because he is a peace-lover and not a killer, so the just person

living in the real world must experience some degree of

dissatisfaction with his attempts to give each person his due. The

pleasures of exercising the ethical virtues are, in normal

circumstances, mixed with pain. Unalloyed pleasure is available to us

only when we remove ourselves from the all-too-human world and

contemplate the rational order of the cosmos. No human life can

consist solely in these pure pleasures; and in certain circumstances

one may owe it to one’s community to forego a philosophical life

and devote oneself to the good of the city. But the paradigms of human

happiness are those people who are lucky enough to devote much of

their time to the study of a world more orderly than the human world

we inhabit.

Although Aristotle argues for the superiority of the philosophical

life in X.7–8, he says in X.9, the final chapter of the

Ethics, that his project is not yet complete, because we can

make human beings virtuous, or good even to some small degree, only if

we undertake a study of the art of legislation. The final section of

the Ethics is therefore intended as a prolegomenon to

Aristotle’s political writings. We must investigate the kinds of

political systems exhibited by existing Greek cities, the forces that

destroy or preserve cities, and the best sort of political order.

Although the study of virtue Aristotle has just completed is meant to

be helpful to all human beings who have been brought up

well—even those who have no intention of pursuing a political

career—it is also designed to serve a larger purpose. Human

beings cannot achieve happiness, or even something that approximates

happiness, unless they live in communities that foster good habits and

provide the basic equipment of a well-lived life.

The study of the human good has therefore led to two conclusions: The

best life is not to be found in the practice of politics. But the well

being of whole communities depends on the willingness of some to lead

a second-best life—a life devoted to the study and practice of

the art of politics, and to the expression of those qualities of

thought and passion that exhibit our rational self-mastery.

Glossary

appearances: phainomena

beautiful: kalon

clear: saphes

complete (verb, also: to perfect): telein

condition: hexis

continence (literally: mastery): enkrateia

continent: enkratês

disposition: hexis

emotion: pathos

evil: kakos, phaulos

excellence: aretê

feeling: pathos

fine: kalon

flourishing: eudaimonia

friendship: philia; philein (the verb cognate to

the noun “philia”, can sometimes be translated

“like” or even “love”)

function: ergon

good will: eunoia

happiness: eudaimonia

happy: eudaimon

impetuosity: propeteia

incontinence (literally: lack of mastery): akrasia

incontinent: akratês

intuitive understanding: nous

live well: eu zên

practical wisdom: phronêsis

science: epistêmê

standard: horos

state: hexis

task: ergon

virtue: aretê

weakness: astheneia

work: ergon

Further Reading

A. Single-Authored Overviews

Broadie 1991; Bostock 2000; Burger 2008; Gauthier & Jolif

1958–59; Hall 2019; Hardie 1980; Pakaluk 2005; Price 2011; Reeve

2012a; Urmson 1987.

B. Anthologies

Anton & Preus (eds.) 1991; Barnes, Schofield, & Sorabji (eds.)

1977; Bartlett & Collins (eds.) 1999; Engstrom & Whiting

(eds.) 1996; Heinaman (ed.) 1995; Kraut (ed.) 2006b; Miller (ed.)

2011; Natali (ed.) 2009; Pakaluk & Pearson (eds.) 2010; Polansky

(ed.) 2014; Roche (ed.) 1988c; Rorty (ed.) 1980; Sherman (ed.) 1999;

Sim (ed.) 1995.

C. Studies of Particular Topics

C.1 The Chronological Order of Aristotle’s Ethical Treatises

Kenny 1978, 1979, 1992; Rowe 1971.

C.2 The Methodology and Metaphysics of Ethical Theory

Barnes 1980; Berryman 2019; J.M. Cooper 1999 (ch. 12); Frede 2012;

Heinaman (ed.) 1995; Irwin 1988b; Karbowski 2014b, 2015a, 2015b, 2019;

Kontos 2011; Kraut 1998; McDowell 1995; Nussbaum 1985, 1986 (chs

8–9); Reeve 1992 (ch. 1), 2012b; Roche 1988b, 1992; Scott 2015;

Segvic 2002; Shields 2012a; Zingano 2007b.

C.3 The Human Good and the Human Function

Annas 1993 (ch. 18); Barney 2008; Broadie 2005, 2007a; Charles 1999;

Clark 1975 (14–27, 145–63); J.M. Cooper 1986 (chs 1, 3),

1999 (chs 9, 13); Curzer 1991; Gadamer 1986; Gerson 2004; Gomez-Lobo

1989; Heinaman 2002, 2007; Irwin 2012; Keyt 1978; Korsgaard 1986a,

1986b; Kraut 1979a, 1979b, 1989, 2002 (ch. 3); Lawrence 1993, 1997,

2001; G.R. Lear 2000; J. Lear 2000; MacDonald 1989; Natali 2010;

Nussbaum 1986 (chs 11, 12); Purinton 1998; Reeve 1992 (chs 3, 4);

Roche 1988a; Santas 2001 (chs 6–7); Scott 1999, 2000; Segvic

2004; Suits 1974; Van Cleemput 2006; Wedin 1981; N. White 2002, 2006;

S. White 1992; Whiting 1986, 1988; Wielenberg 2004; Williams 1985 (ch.

3).

C.4 The Nature of Virtue and Accounts of Particular Virtues

Brickhouse 2003; Brown 1997; Brunschwig 1996; Clark 1975

(84–97); N. Cooper 1989; Curzer 1990, 1995, 1996, 1997, 2005,

2012; Di Muzio 2000; Gardiner 2001; Gottlieb 1991, 1994a, 1994b, 1996,

2009; Halper 1999; Hardie 1978; Hursthouse 1988; Hutchinson 1986;

Irwin 1988a; Jimenez 2020; Kraut 2002 (ch. 4), 2012, 2013; Leunissen

2012, 2013, 2017; Lorenz 2009; McKerlie 2001; Pakaluk 2004; Pearson

2006, 2007; Peterson 1988; Russell 2012a; Santas 2001 (ch. 8);

Scaltsas 1995; Schütrumpf 1989; Sherman 1989, 1997; Sim 2007;

Taylor 2004; Telfer 1989–90; Tuozzo 1995; Whiting 1996; Young

1988; Yu 2007.

C.5 Practical Reasoning, Moral Psychology, and Action

Broadie 1998; Charles 1984, 2007; Coope 2012; J. Cooper 1986 (ch. 1),

1999 (chs 10, 11, 19); Dahl 1984; Destrée 2007;

Engberg-Pedersen 1983; Fortenbaugh 1975; Gottlieb, 2021;

Gröngross 2007; Hursthouse 1984; Kontos 2018; Kontos 2021; Kraut

2006a; Lorenz 2006; McDowell 1996a, 1996b, 1998; McKerlie 1998; Meyer

1993; Milo 1966; Moss 2011, 2012; Natali (ed.) 2009; Nussbaum 1986

(ch. 10); Olfert 2017; Pakaluk & Pearson (eds.) 2010;

Pickavé & Whiting 2008; Politis 1998; Reeve 1992 (ch. 2),

2013; Segvic 2009a; Sherman 2000; Taylor 2003b; Walsh 1963; Zingano

2007a.

C.6 Pleasure

Gosling &Taylor 1982 (chs 11–17); Gottlieb 1993; Natali

(ed.) 2009; Owen 1971; Pearson 2012; Rorty 1974; Taylor 2003a, 2003b;

Urmson 1967; Warren 2009; Wolfsdorf 2013 (ch. 6).

C.7 Friendship

Annas 1977, 1993 (ch. 12); Brewer 2005; J.M. Cooper 1999 (chs 14, 15);

Hitz 2011; Kahn 1981; Milgram 1987; Nehamas 2010; Pakaluk 1998; Pangle

2003; Price 1989 (chs 4–7); Rogers 1994; Schollmeier 1994;

Sherman 1987; Stern-Gillet 1995; Walker 2014; Whiting 1991.

C.8 Feminism and Aristotle

Freeland 1998; Karbowski 2014a; Modrak 1994; Ward (ed.) 1996.

C.9 Aristotle and Contemporary Ethics

Bielskis 2020; Broadie 2006; Chappell (ed.) 2006; Garver 2006; Gill

(ed.) 2005; Kraut 2018; LeBar 2013; MacIntyre 1999; Peters 2014;

Russell 2012b; Stohr 2003, 2009; Wiggins 2009.

D. Bibliographies

Lockwood 2005.

Bibliography

Primary Literature

Nicomachean Ethics

2012, Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Robert C.

Bartlett, and Susan D. Collins (eds/trans.), Chicago: The University

of Chicago Press.

2000, Nicomachean Ethics, Roger Crisp (ed./trans.),

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9780511802058

1999, Nicomachean Ethics, Terence H. Irwin (ed./trans.),

Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co. With Introduction, Notes, and

Glossary. Second edition.

2014, Nicomachean Ethics, C.D.C. Reeve, Indianapolis:

Hackett Publishing Co.

1984, Nicomachean Ethics, W.D. Ross (trans.), revised by

J.O. Urmson, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, The Revised

Oxford Translation, vol. 2, Jonathan Barnes (ed.), Princeton:

Princeton University Press, 1984.

2002, Nicomachean Ethics, Christopher Rowe (trans.),

Oxford: Oxford University Press, With philosophical introduction and

commentary by Sarah Broadie.

Eudemian Ethics

2013, Eudemian Ethics, (Cambridge Texts in the History

of Philosophy), Brad Inwood and Raphael Woolf (eds./trans.),

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9781139043281

2011, Eudemian Ethics, (Oxford World’s Classics),

Anthony Kenny (ed./trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

1984, Eudemian Ethics, J. Solomon (trans.), in The

Complete Works of Aristotle, The Revised Oxford Translation,

volume 2, Jonathan Barnes (ed.), Princeton: Princeton University

Press.

1952, Eudemian Ethics, H. Rackham (trans.), in the Loeb

Classical Library, Aristotle, vol. 20, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

1992, Aristotle’s Eudemian Ethics: Books I, II, and

VIII, M.J. Woods (trans.), Second edition, Oxford: Clarendon

Press.

Secondary Literature

Annas, Julia, 1977, “Plato and Aristotle on Friendship and

Altruism”, Mind, 86: 532–54.

doi:10.1093/mind/LXXXVI.344.532

–––, 1993, The Morality of Happiness,

New York: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/0195096525.001.0001

Anton, John P. & Anthony Preus (eds.), 1991,

Aristotle’s Ethics: Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy,

vol. 5, Albany, NY: The State University of New York Press, 1991.

Austin, J. L., 1957 [1961], “A Plea for Excuses: The

Presidential Address”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian

Society, 57: 1–30. Reprinted in his Philosophical

Papers, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961.

doi:10.1093/aristotelian/57.1.1

Barnes, Jonathan, 1980, “Aristotle and the Methods of

Ethics”, Revue Internationale de la Philosophie,

34(133/134): 490–511.

Barnes, Jonathan, Malcolm Schofield, and Richard Sorabji (eds.),

1977, Articles on Aristotle, vol. 2, Ethics and

Politics, London: Duckworth, 1977.

Barney, Rachel, 2008, “Aristotle’s Argument for a

Human Function”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

34(Summer): 293–322.

Bartlett, Robert C. & Susan D. Collins (eds.), 1999,

Action and Contemplation, Albany, NY: State University of New

York Press.

Berryman, Sylvia, 2019, Aristotle on the Sources of Ethical

Life, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bielskis, Andrius, Eleni Leontsinia, and Kelvin Knight (eds.),

2020, Virtue Ethics and Contemporary Aristotelianism: Modernity,

Conflict, and Politics, London: Bloomsbury Academic.

Bobonich, Christopher and Pierre Destree (eds.), 2007, Akrasia

in Greek Philosophy: From Socrates to Plotinus, Leiden:

Brill.

Bostock, David, 2000, Aristotle’s Ethics, Oxford:

Oxford University Press.

Brewer, Talbot, 2005, “Virtues We Can Share: Friendship and

Aristotelian Ethical Theory”, Ethics, 115(4):

721–758. doi:10.1086/430489

Brickhouse, Thomas C., 2003, “Does Aristotle Have a

Consistent Account of Vice?” Review of Metaphysics,

57(1): 3–23.

Broadie, Sarah, 1991, Ethics with Aristotle, New York:

Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195085604.001.0001

–––, 1998, “Interpreting Aristotle’s

Directions”, in Gentzler 1998: 291–306.

–––, 2005, “On the Idea of the Summum

Bonum”, in Gill 2005: 41–58 (ch. 2). Reprinted in

Broadie 2007b: 135–152 (ch. 9).

–––, 2006, “Aristotle and Contemporary

Ethics”, in Kraut 2006: 342–361. Reprinted in Broadie

2007b: 113–134. doi:10.1002/9780470776513.ch16

–––, 2007a, “What Should We Mean by

‘The Highest Good’?”, in Broadie 2007b:

153–165 (ch. 10).

–––, 2007b, Aristotle and Beyond: Essays on

Metaphysics and Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9780511551086

Brown, Lesley, 1997, “What is the Mean Relative to Us in

Aristotle’s Ethics?” Phronesis, 42:

77–93.

Brunschwig, Jacques, 1996, “The Aristotelian Theory of

Equity”, in Michael Frede & Gisela Striker (eds.),

Rationality in Greek Thought, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp.

115–155.

Burger, Ronna, 2008, Aristotle’s Dialogue with Socrates:

on the Nicomachean Ethics, Chicago: The University of Chicago

Press.

Chappell, Timothy (ed.), 2006, Values and Virtues:

Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon

Press.

Charles, David, 1984, Aristotle’s Philosophy of

Action, London: Duckworth.

–––, 1999, “Aristotle on Well-Being and

Intellectual Contemplation”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian

Society (Supplementary Volume), 73: 205–223.

–––, 2007, “Aristotle’s Weak

Akrates: What does her Ignorance Consist in?”, in Bobonich and

Destree 2007: 139–166.

Clark, Stephen R.L., 1975, Aristotle’s Man: Speculations

upon Aristotelian Anthropology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198245162.001.0001

Coope, Ursula, 2012, “Why does Aristotle Think that Ethical

Virtue is Required for Practical Wisdom?” Phronesis,

57(2): 142–163. doi:10.1163/156852812X628998

Cooper, John M., 1986, Reason and Human Good in

Aristotle, Indianapolis: Hackett.

–––, 1999, Reason and Emotion: Essays on

Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory, Princeton: Princeton

University Press.

Cooper, Neil, 1989, “Aristotle’s Crowning

Virtue”, Apeiron, 22(3): 191–205.

doi:10.1515/APEIRON.1989.22.3.191

Curzer, Howard J., 1990, “A Great Philosopher’s Not So

Great Account of Great Virtue: Aristotle’s Treatment of

‘Greatness of Soul’”, Canadian Journal of

Philosophy, 20(4): 517–537.

Curzer, Howard J., 1991, “The Supremely Happy Life in

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics”,

Apeiron, 24(1): 47–69.

doi:10.1515/APEIRON.1991.24.1.47

–––, 1995, “Aristotle’s Account of

the Virtue of Justice”, Apeiron, 28(3): 207–238.

doi:10.1515/APEIRON.1995.28.3.207

–––, 1996, “A Defense of Aristotle’s

Doctrine that Virtue Is a Mean”, Ancient Philosophy,

16(1): 129–138. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199616116

–––, 1997, “Aristotle’s Account of

the Virtue of Temperance in Nicomachean Ethics III

10–11”, Journal of the History of Philosophy,

35(1): 5–25. doi:10.1353/hph.1997.0008

–––, 2005, “How Good People Do Bad Things:

Aristotle on the Misdeeds of the Virtuous”, Oxford Studies

in Ancient Philosophy, 28(Summer): 233–272.

–––, 2012, Aristotle and the Virtues,

Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199693726.001.0001

Dahl, Norman O., 1984, Practical Reason, Aristotle, and

Weakness of Will, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota

Press.

Destrée, Pierre, 2007, “Aristotle on the Causes of

Akrasia”, in Bobonich and Destree 2007: 139–166.

Di Muzio, Gianluca, 2000, “Aristotle on Improving

One’s Character”, Phronesis, 45(3):

205–219. doi:10.1163/156852800510180

Engberg-Pedersen, Troels, 1983, Aristotle’s Theory of

Moral Insight, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Engstrom, Stephen and Jennifer Whiting (eds.), 1996,

Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics, Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Fortenbaugh, W.W., 1975, Aristotle on Emotion, London:

Duckworth.

Frede, Dorothea, 2012, “The Endoxon Mystique: What

Endoxa Are and What They are Not”, Oxford Studies

in Ancient Philosophy, 43(Winter): 185–216.

Freeland, Cynthia (ed.), 1998, Feminist Interpretations of

Aristotle, University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University

Press.

Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 1986, The Idea of the Good in

Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy, New Haven, CT: Yale University

Press.

Gardiner, Stephen M., 2001, “Aristotle’s Basic and

Non-Basic Virtues”, Oxford Studies in Ancient

Philosophy, 20(Summer): 261–295.

Garver, Eugene, 2006, Confronting Aristotle’s Ethics:

Ancient and Modern Morality, Chicago: The University of Chicago

Press.

Gauthier, R.A. & J.Y. Jolif, 1958–9, Aristote:

L’Ethique à Nicomaque, 3 vols. Louvain: Publications

Universitaires de Louvain.

Gentzler, Jyl (ed.), 1998, Method in Ancient Philosophy,

Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Gerson, Lloyd, 2004, “Platonism in Aristotle’s

Ethics”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

27(Winter): 217–48.

Gill, Christopher (ed.), 2005, Virtue, Norms, and Objectivity:

Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon

Press.

Gomez-Lobo, Alfonso, 1989, “The Ergon

Inference”, Phronesis, 34(1): 170–84.

doi:10.1163/156852889X00116

Gosling, J.C.B. & C.C.W. Taylor, 1982, The Greeks on

Pleasure, Oxford: Clarendon Press, Chapters 11–17.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198246664.001.0001

Gottlieb, Paula, 1991, “Aristotle and Protagoras: The Good

Human Being as the Measure of Goods”, Apeiron, 24(1):

25–45. doi:10.1515/APEIRON.1991.24.1.25

–––, 1993, “Aristotle’s Measure

Doctrine and Pleasure”, Archiv für Geschichte der

Philosophie, 75(1): 31–46. doi:

10.1515/agph.1993.75.1.31

–––, 1994a, “Aristotle’s

‘Nameless’ Virtues”, Apeiron, 27(1):

1–15. doi:10.1515/APEIRON.1994.27.1.1

–––, 1994b, “Aristotle on Dividing the

Soul and Uniting the Virtues”, Phronesis, 39(3):

275–290. doi:10.1163/156852894321052081

–––, 1996, “Aristotle’s Ethical

Egoism”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 77(1):

1–18. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.1996.tb00155.x

–––, 2009, The Virtue of Aristotle’s

Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9780511581526

–––, 2021, Aristotle on Thought and

Feeling, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Gröngross, Gösta, 2007, “Listening to Reason in

Aristotle’s Moral Psychology”, Oxford Studies in

Ancient Philosophy, 32(Summer): 251–272.

Hall, Edith, 2019, Aristotle’s Way: How Ancient Wisdom

Can Change Your Life, London: The Bodley Head.

Halper, Edward, 1999, “The Unity of the Virtues in

Aristotle”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 17:

115–144.

Hardie, W.F.R., 1978, “Magnanimity in

Aristotle’s Ethics”, Phronesis, 78(1):

63–79. doi:10.1163/156852878X00226

–––, 1980, Aristotle’s Ethical

Theory, second edition, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198246329.001.0001

Heinaman, Robert (ed.), 1995, Aristotle and Moral

Realism, Boulder, CO: Westview.

–––, 2002, “The Improvability of

Eudaimonia in the Nicomachean Ethics”, Oxford Studies in

Ancient Philosophy, 23: 99–145.

–––, 2007, “Eudaimonia as an Activity in

Nicomachean Ethics I.8–12”, Oxford Studies in Ancient

Philosophy, 33(Winter): 221–254.

Hitz, Zena, 2011, “Aristotle on Self-Knowledge and

Friendship” Philosophers’ Imprint, 11(12):

1–28.

[Hitz 2011 available online]

Hursthouse, Rosalind, 1984, “Acting and Feeling in

Character: Nicomachean Ethics 3.1”, Phronesis,

29(3): 252–266. doi:10.1163/156852884X00030

–––, 1988, “Moral Habituation”,

Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 6: 201–219.

Hutchinson, D.S., 1986, The Virtues of Aristotle, London:

Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Irwin, Terence H., 1988a, “Disunity in the Aristotelian

Virtues”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

Supplementary Volume 1988: 61–78.

–––, 1988b, Aristotle’s First

Principles, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

doi:10.1093/0198242905.001.0001

–––, 2012, “Conceptions of Happiness in

the Nicomachean Ethics”, in Shields 2012b:

495–428

Jimenez, Marta, 2020, Aristotle on Shame and Learning to Be

Good, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kahn, Charles H., 1981, “Aristotle and Altruism”,

Mind, 90(357): 20–40. doi:10.1093/mind/XC.357.20

Karbowski, Joseph, 2014a, “Aristotle on the Rational

Abilities of Women”, Apeiron, 47(4): 435–460.

doi:10.1515/apeiron-2013-0061

–––, 2014b, “Endoxa, Facts, and

the Starting Points of the Nicomachean Ethics”, in

Karen Margrethe Nielsen and Devon Henry (eds.), Bridging the Gap

Between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511846397.007

–––, 2015a, “Is Aristotle’s

Eudemian Ethics Quasi-Mathematical?” Apeiron,

48(3): 368–386. doi:10.1515/apeiron-2014-0046

–––, 2015b, “Phainomena as

Witnesses and Examples: The Methodology of Eudemian Ethics

I.6” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 49:

193–225.

–––, 2019, Aristotle’s Method in

Ethics: Philosophy in Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Kenny, Anthony, 1978, The Aristotelian Ethics: A Study of The

Relationship between the Eudemian and Nicomachean Ethics of

Aristotle, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198245544.001.0001

–––, 1979, Aristotle’s Theory of the

Will, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

–––, 1992, Aristotle on the Perfect

Life, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198240174.001.0001

Keyt, David, 1978, “Intellectualism in Aristotle”,

Paideia, 7: 138–157.

Kontos, Pavlos, 2011, Aristotle’s Moral Realism

Reconsidered: Phenomenological Ethics, New York: Routledge.

–––, (ed.), 2018, Evil in Aristotle,

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

–––, 2021, Aristotle on the Scope of

Practical Reason: Spectators, Legislators, Hopes, and Evils, New

York: Routledge.

Korsgaard, Christine M., 1986a, “Aristotle on Function and

Virtue”, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 3(3):

259–279.

–––, 1986b, “Aristotle and Kant on the

Source of Value”, Ethics, 96(3): 486–505.

doi:10.1086/292771

Kraut, Richard, 1979a, “Two Conceptions of Happiness”,

Philosophical Review, 88(2): 167–197.

doi:10.2307/2184505

–––, 1979b, “The Peculiar Function of

Human Beings”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 9(3):

53–62. doi:10.1080/00455091.1979.10716263

–––, 1989, Aristotle on the Human Good,

Princeton: Princeton University Press.

–––, 1998, “Aristotle on Method and Moral

Education”, in Gentzler 1998: 271–290.

–––, 2002, Aristotle: Political

Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

–––, 2006a, “Doing Without Morality:

Reflections on the Meaning of Dein in Aristotle’s Nicomachean

Ethics”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

30(Summer): 169–200.

––– (ed.), 2006b, The Blackwell Guide to

Aristotle’s Ethics, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

doi:10.1002/9780470776513

–––, 2012, “Aristotle on Becoming Good:

Habituation, Reflection, and Perception”, in Shields 2012b:

529–557.

–––, 2013, “An Aesthetic Reading of

Aristotle’s Ethics”, in Verity Harte and Melissa Lane

(eds.), Politeia: Essays in Honour of Malcolm Schofield,

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 231–250.

doi:10.1017/CBO9781139096843.016

–––, 2018, The Quality of Life: Aristotle

Revised, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lawrence, Gavin, 1993, “Aristotle and the Ideal Life”,

Philosophical Review, 102(1): 1–34.

doi:10.2307/2185651

–––, 1997, “Nonaggregatability,

Inclusiveness, and the Theory of Focal Value: Nicomachean

Ethics I.7 1097b16–20”, Phronesis, 42(1):

32–76. doi:10.1163/156852897321163409

–––, 2001, “The Function of the Function

Argument”, Ancient Philosophy, 21(2): 445–475.

doi:10.5840/ancientphil200121227

Lear, Gabriel Richardson, 2000, Happy Lives and the Highest

Good: An Essay on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics,

Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Lear, Jonathan, 2000, Happiness, Death, and the Remainder of

Life, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

LeBar, Mark, 2013, The Value of Living Well, New York:

Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199931118.001.0001

Leunissen, Mariska, 2012, “Aristotle on Natural Character

and Its Implications for Moral Development”, Journal of the

History of Philosophy, 50(4): 507–530.

doi:10.1353/hph.2012.0062

–––, 2013, “’Becoming good starts

with nature’Aristotle on the Heritability and Advantages of Good

Natural Character”, Oxford Studies in Ancient

Philosophy, 44: 99–128.

–––, 2017, From Natural Character to Moral

Virtue in Aristotle, New York: Oxford University Press.

Lockwood, Thornton C., 2005 “A Topical Bibliography of

Scholarship on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: 1880 to

2004”, Journal of Philosophical Research, 30:

1–116. doi:10.5840/jpr20053048

Lorenz, Hendrik, 2006, The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in

Plato and Aristotle, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

doi:10.1093/0199290636.001.0001

–––, 2009, “Virtue of Character in

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics”, Oxford Studies in

Ancient Philosophy, 37(Winter): 177–212.

MacDonald, Scott, 1989, “Aristotle and the Homonymy of the

Good”, Archiv Für Geschichte der Philosophie,

71(2): 150–174. doi:10.1515/agph.1989.71.2.150

MacIntyre, Alasdair, 1999, Dependent Rational Animals: Why

Human Beings Need the Virtues, Chicago: Open Court.

McDowell, John, 1995, “Eudaimonism and Realism in

Aristotle’s Ethics”, Heinaman 1995: 201–208.

Reprinted in McDowell 2009: 23–40 (ch. 2).

–––, 1996a, “Deliberation and Moral

Development in Aristotle’s Ethics”, Engstrom & Whiting

1996: 19–35. Reprinted in McDowell 2009: 41–58 (ch.

3).

–––, 1996b, “Incontinence and Practical

Wisdom in Aristotle”, in Sabina Lovibond & Stephen G.

Williams (eds.), Essays for David Wiggins: Identity, Truth and

Value, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 167–197. Reprinted in

McDowell 2009: 59–76 (ch. 4).

–––, 1998, “Some Issues in

Aristotle’s Moral Psychology”, in Mind, Value, and

Reality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp.

23–49.

–––, 2009, The Engaged Intellect:

Philosophical Essays, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

Press.

McKerlie, Dennis, 1998, “Aristotle and Egoism”,

Southern Journal of Philosophy, 36(4): 531–555.

doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.1998.tb01769.x

–––, 2001, “Aristotle’s Theory of

Justice”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39(1):

119–141. doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.2001.tb01809.x

Meyer, Susan Sauvé, 1993, Aristotle on Moral

Responsibility, Oxford: Blackwell.

Milgram, Elijah, 1987, “Aristotle on Making Other

Selves”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17(2):

361–376. doi:10.1080/00455091.1987.10716441

Miller, Jon (ed.), 2011, Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics:

A Critical Guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Milo, Ronald D., 1966, Aristotle on Practical Knowledge and

Weakness of Will, The Hague: Mouton.

Modrak, Deborah, 1994, “Aristotle: Women, Deliberation, and

Nature”, in Bat-Ami Bar On (ed.), Engendering Origins:

Critical Feminist Readings in Plato and Aristotle, Albany, NY:

State University of New York Press, pp. 207–22.

Moss, Jessica, 2011, “‘Virtue Makes the Goal

Right’ Virtue and Phronesis in Aristotle’s

Ethics”, Phronesis, 56(3): 204–261.

doi:10.1163/156852811X575907

–––, 2012, Aristotle on the Apparent Good:

Perception, Phantasia, Thought, and Desire, Oxford: Oxford

University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199656349.001.0001

Natali, Carlo (ed.), 2009, Aristotle’s

‘Nicomachean Ethics’, Book VII, (Symposia

Aristotelia), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

–––, 2010, “Posterior Analytics

and the Definition of Happiness in NE I”,

Phronesis, 55(4): 304–324.

doi:10.1163/156852810X523905

Nehamas, Alexander, 2010, “Aristotelian Philia,

Modern Friendship”, Oxford Studies in Ancient

Philosophy, 39: 213–47.

Nussbaum, Martha C., 1985, “The Discernment of Perception:

An Aristotelian Conception of Private and Public Rationality”,

Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient

Philosophy, 1: 151–201. Reprinted in her Love’s

Knowledge, New York: Oxford University Press, 1990, pp.

54–105. doi:10.1163/2213441785X00102

–––, 1986, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck

and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Olfert, Christiana, 2017, Aristotle on Practical Truth,

New York: Oxford University Press.

Owen, G.E.L., 1971, “Aristotelian Pleasures”,

Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 72: 135–152.

Reprinted in his, Logic, Science and Dialectic: Collected Papers

in Greek Philosophy, M. Nussbaum (ed.), Ithaca, NY: Cornell

University Press, pp. 334–46.

Pakaluk, Michael, 1998, Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books

VIII and IX, (Clarendon Aristotle Series), Oxford: Clarendon

Press.

–––, 2004, “The Meaning of Aristotelian

Magnanimity”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

26(Summer): 241–276.

–––, 2005, Aristotle’s Nicomachean

Ethics: An Introduction, Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Pakaluk, Michael and Giles Pearson (eds.), 2010, Moral

Psychology and Human Action in Aristotle, Oxford: Oxford

University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199546541.001.0001

Pangle, Lorraine Smith, 2003, Aristotle and the Philosophy of

Friendship, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9780511498282

Pearson, Giles, 2006, “Aristotle on Acting Unjustly without

Being Unjust”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

30(Summer): 211–234.

–––, 2007, “Phronesis as a Mean in the

Eudemian Ethics”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

32(Summer): 273–296.

–––, 2012, Aristotle on Desire,

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9781139161770

Peters, Julia, 2014, Aristotelian Ethics in Contemporary

Perspective, New York: Routlege.

Peterson, Sandra, 1988, “’Horos’

(limit) in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics”,

Phronesis, 33(1): 233–250.

doi:10.1163/156852888X00180

Pickavé, Martin and Jennifer Whiting, 2008,

“Nicomachean Ethics 7.3 on Akratic Ignorance”, Oxford

Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 34(Summer): 323–372.

Polansky, Ronald (ed.), 2014, The Cambridge Companion to

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press. doi:10.1017/CCO9781139022484

Politis, Vasilis, 1998, “Aristotle’s Advocacy of

Non-Productive Action”, Ancient Philosophy, 18(2):

353–379. doi:10.5840/ancientphil199818238

Price, A.W., 1989, Love and Friendship in Plato and

Aristotle, New York: Oxford University Press, Chapters 4–7.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198248996.001.0001

–––, 2011, Virtue and Reason in Plato and

Aristotle, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199609611.001.0001

Purinton, Jeffrey S., 1998, “Aristotle’s Definition of

Happiness (NE I.7 1098a16–18)”, Oxford Studies in

Ancient Philosophy, 16: 259–298.

Reeve, C.D.C., 1992, Practices of Reason: Aristotle’s

Nicomachean Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198235651.001.0001

–––, 2012a, Action, Contemplation, and

Happiness: An Essay on Aristotle, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

–––, 2012b, “Aristotle’s

Philosophical Method”, in Shields 2012b: 150–170.

–––, 2013, Aristotle on Practical Wisdom:

Nicomachean Ethics VI, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

Press.

Roche, Timothy D., 1988a, “Ergon and

Eudaimonia in Nicomachean Ethics I: Reconsidering

the Intellectualist Interpretation”, Journal of the History

of Philosophy, 26(2): 175–194.

doi:10.1353/hph.1988.0034

–––, 1988b, “On the Alleged Metaphysical

Foundation of Aristotle’s Ethics”, Ancient

Philosophy, 8(1): 49–62.

doi:10.5840/ancientphil19888120

––– (ed.), 1988c, Aristotle’s

Ethics, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, Spindel

Conference, Supplement 27(S1).

–––, 1992, “In Defense of an Alternative

View of the Foundation of Aristotle’s Moral Theory”,

Phronesis, 37(1): 46–84.

doi:10.1163/156852892321052650

Rogers, Kelly, 1994, “Aristotle on Loving Another For His

Own Sake”, Phronesis, 39(3): 291–302.

doi:10.1163/156852894321052090

Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg, 1974, “The Place of Pleasure

in Aristotle’s Ethics”, Mind, 83(332):

481–93. doi:10.1093/mind/LXXXIII.332.481

––– (ed.), 1980, Essays on Aristotle’s

Ethics, Berkeley: University of California Press.

Rowe, C.J., 1971, The Eudemian and Nicomachean Ethics—a

Study in the Development of Aristotle’s Thought, Cambridge:

Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, suppl. no. 3.

Russell, Daniel C., 2012a, “Aristotle’s Virtues of

Greatness”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

Supplementary Volume 2012, Virtue and Happiness: Essays in Honour

of Julia Annas, pp. 115–147.

–––, 2012b, Happiness for Humans,

Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199583683.001.0001

Santas, Gerasimos, 2001, Goodness and Justice: Plato,

Aristotle, and the Moderns, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Scaltsas, Theodore, 1995, “Reciprocal Justice in

Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics”, Archiv

für Geschichte der Philosophie, 77(3): 248–262.

doi:10.1515/agph.1995.77.3.248

Schollmeier, Paul, 1994, Other Selves: Aristotle on Personal

and Political Friendship, Albany, NY: State University of New

York Press.

Schütrumpf, Eckart, 1989, “Magnanimity,

Mεγαλοψυχία,

and the System of Aristotle’s Nicomachean

Ethics”, Archiv für Geschichte der

Philosophie, 71(1): 10–22.

doi:10.1515/agph.1989.71.1.10

Scott, Dominic, 1999, “Aristotle on Well-Being and

Intellectual Contemplation: Primary and Secondary Eudaimonia”,

Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 73:

225–242.

–––, 2000, “Aristotle on Posthumous

Fortune”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

18(Summer): 211–230.

–––, 2015, Levels of Argument: A Comparative

Study of Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Nicomachean

Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199249640.001.0001

Segvic, Heda, 2002, “Aristotle’s Metaphysics of

Action”, Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse /

Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 5: 23–53.

Reprint in Segvic 2009b: 111–143 (ch. 5).

–––, 2004, “Aristotle on the Varieties of

Goodness”, Apeiron, 37: 151–176. Reprinted in

Segvic 2009b: 89–110 (ch. 4).

–––, 2009a, “Deliberation and Choice in

Aristotle”, in Segvic 2009b: 144–171. Also appeared in

Pakaluk and Pearson 2010: 159–186.

doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199546541.003.0008

–––, 2009b, From Protagoras to Aristotle:

Essays in Ancient Moral Philosophy, Myles Burnyeat (ed.),

Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Sherman, Nancy, 1987, “Aristotle on Friendship and the

Shared Life”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,

47(4): 589–613. doi:10.2307/2107230

–––, 1989, The Fabric of Character:

Aristotle’s Theory of Virtue, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

doi:10.1093/0198239173.001.0001

–––, 1997, Making a Virtue of Necessity:

Aristotle and Kant on Virtue, Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511624865

––– (ed.), 1999, Aristotle’s Ethics:

Critical Essays, Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.

–––, 2000, “Is the Ghost of Aristotle

Haunting Freud’s House?” Proceedings of the Boston

Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 16(1): 63–81.

doi:10.1163/2213441700X00079

Shields, Christopher, 2012a, “Goodness is Meant in Many

Ways”, in G. Rudebusch and J. Hardy (eds.) Grundlagen der

Antiken Ethik / Foundations of Ancient Ethics, Goettingen:

Vanderhoek & Ruprecht, pp. 185–199.

Shields, Christopher (ed.), 2012b, The Oxford Handbook of

Aristotle, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195187489.001.0001

Sim, May (ed.), 1995, The Crossroads of Norm and Nature,

Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.

–––, 2007, Remastering Morals with Aristotle

and Confucius, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9780511497841

Stern-Gillet, Suzanne, 1995, Aristotle’s Philosophy of

Friendship, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

Stohr, Karen, 2003, “Moral Cacophony: When Continence is a

Virtue”, Journal of Ethics, 7(4): 339–363.

doi:10.1023/A:1026111711649

–––, 2009, “Minding Others’

Business”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 90(1):

116–139. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.2009.01331.x

Suits, Bernard, 1974, “Aristotle on the Function of Man:

Fallacies, Heresies and other Entertainments”, Canadian

Journal of Philosophy, 4(1): 23–40.

doi:10.1080/00455091.1974.10716919

Taylor, C.C.W., 1988, “Urmson on Aristotle on

Pleasure”, in J. Dancy, J. M. E. Moravcsik, and C. C. W. Taylor

(eds.), Human Agency: Language, Duty, and Value. Philosophical

Essays in Honor of J. O. Urmson, Stanford, CA: Stanford

University Press, pp. 120–132. Reprinted in Taylor 2008:

107–120 (ch. 7).

–––, 2003a, “Pleasure: Aristotle’s

Response to Plato”, in Robert Heinaman (ed.), Plato and

Aristotle’s Ethics, Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing, pp.

1–20.

–––, 2003b, “Aristotle on the Practical

Intellect”, (in German, trans. R. May, with the assistance of A.

W. Müller), in T. Buchheim, H. Flashar, and R. A. H. King (eds.),

Kann man heute noch etwas anfangen mit Aristoteles?, Hamburg:

Meiner Verlag, pp. 142–162. Reprinted (in English) in Taylor

2008: 204–222 (ch. 12).

–––, 2004, “Wisdom and Courage in the

Protagoras and the Nicomachean Ethics”, (in Italian, trans. S.

Casertano), in G. Casertano (ed.), Il Protagora di Platone:

struttura e problematiche, Naples: Loffredo Editore, Naples, pp.

716–728. Reprinted (in English) in Taylor 2008: 281–294

(ch. 16).

–––, 2008, Pleasure, Mind, and Soul:

Selected Papers in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University

Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199226399.001.0001

Telfer, Elizabeth, 1989–90, “The Unity of Moral

Virtues in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics”,

Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 91:

35–48.

Tuozzo, Thomas M., 1995, “Contemplation, the Noble, and the

Mean: The Standard of Moral Virtue in Aristotle’s Ethics”,

Apeiron, special issue Aristotle, Virtue and the

Mean, 28(4): 129–154.

doi:10.1515/APEIRON.1995.28.4.129.

Urmson, J.O., 1967, “Aristotle on Pleasure”, in J.M.E.

Moravcsik (ed.), Aristotle: A Collection of Critical Essays,

Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, pp. 323–33.

–––, 1987, Aristotle’s Ethics,

Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Van Cleemput, 2006, “Aristotle on Eudaimonia in Nicomachean

Ethics I”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

30(Summer): 127–158.

Walker, Matthew D., 2014, “Aristotle on the Utility and

Choiceworthiness of Friends”, Archiv für Geschichte der

Philosophie, 96(2): 151–182.

doi:10.1515/agph-2014-0008

Walsh, James, 1963, Aristotle’s Conception of Moral

Weakness, New York: Columbia University Press.

Ward, Julie K. (ed.), 1996, Feminism and Ancient

Philosophy, New York: Routledge.

Warren, James, 2009, “Aristotle on Speusippus on Eudoxus on

Pleasure”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,

36(Summer): 249–282.

Wedin, Michael V., 1981, “Aristotle on the Good for

Man”, Mind, 90(358): 243–62.

doi:10.1093/mind/XC.358.243

White, Nicholas P., 2002, Individual and Conflict in Greek

Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

doi:10.1093/0198250592.001.0001

–––, 2006, A Brief History of

Happiness, Malden, ME: Blackwell.

White, Stephen. A., 1992, Sovereign Virtue, Stanford:

Stanford University Press.

Whiting, Jennifer, 1986, “Human Nature and Intellectualism

in Aristotle”, Archiv für Geschichte der

Philosophie, 68(1): 70–95.

doi:10.1515/agph.1986.68.1.70

–––, 1988, “Aristotle’s Function

Argument: A Defense”, Ancient Philosophy, 8(1):

33–48. doi:10.5840/ancientphil19888119

–––, 1991, “Impersonal Friends”,

Monist, 74(1): 3–29. doi:10.5840/monist19917414

–––, 1996, “Self-Love and Authoritative

Virtue: Prolegomenon to a Kantian Reading of Eudemian Ethics

VIII.3”, in Engstrom & Whiting 1996: 162–99.

Wielenberg, Erik J., 2004, “Egoism and

Eudaimonia-Maximization in the Nicomachean

Ethics”, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 26:

277–295.

Wiggins, David, 2009, “What is the Order Among the Varieties

of Goodness? A Question Posed by von Wright; and a Conjecture Made by

Aristotle”, Philosophy, 84(2): 175–200.

doi:10.1017/S0031819109000308

Williams, Bernard, 1985, Ethics and the Limits of

Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Chapter

3.

Wolfsdorf, David, 2013, Pleasure in Ancient Greek

Philosophy, Chapter 6. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

doi:10.1017/CBO9780511667510

Young, Charles M., 1988, “Aristotle on Temperance”

Philosophical Review, 97(4): 521–542.

doi:10.2307/2185414

Yu, Jiyuan, 2007, The Ethics of Confucius and Aristotle:

Mirrors of Virtue, New York: Routledge.

Zingano Marco, 2007a, “Akrasia and the Method of

Ethics”, in Bobonich and Destree 2007: 167–192

–––, 2007b, “Aristotle and the Problems of

Method in Ethics”, Oxford Studies in Ancient

Philosophy, 32(Summer): 297–330.

Academic Tools

How to cite this entry.

Preview the PDF version of this entry at the

Friends of the SEP Society.

Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry

at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).

Enhanced bibliography for this entry

at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

Links to relevant works by Aristotle at Perseus:

Athenian Constitution,

ed. Kenyon. (Greek)

Athenian Constitution,

ed. H. Rackham. (English)

Economics,

(Greek)

Economics,

(English)

Eudemian Ethics,

(Greek)

Eudemian Ethics,

(English)

Metaphysics,

(Greek)

Metaphysics,

(English)

Nicomachean Ethics,

ed. J. Bywater. (Greek)

Nicomachean Ethics,

ed. H. Rackham. (English)

Poetics,

(English)

Politics,

(Greek)

Politics,

(English)

Rhetoric,

ed. W. D. Ross. (Greek)

Rhetoric,

ed. J. H. Freese. (English)

Virtues and Vices,

ed. I. Bekker. (Greek)

Virtues and Vices,

ed. H. Rackham. (English)

Nikomachische Ethik,

in German, translated by Eugen Rolfes, Leipzig: F. Meiner, 1911, at

the Projekt Gutenberg-DE

Related Entries

Aristotle |

character, moral |

egoism |

ethics: virtue |

friendship |

Plato |

pleasure |

wisdom

Copyright © 2022 by

Richard Kraut

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.

The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support

Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

Browse

Table of Contents

What's New

Random Entry

Chronological

Archives

About

Editorial Information

About the SEP

Editorial Board

How to Cite the SEP

Special Characters

Advanced Tools

Accessibility

Contact

Support SEP

Support the SEP

PDFs for SEP Friends

Make a Donation

SEPIA for Libraries

Mirror Sites

View this site from another server:

USA (Main Site)

Philosophy, Stanford University

Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Ethics vs Morals - Difference and Comparison | Diffen

Ethics vs Morals - Difference and Comparison | Diffen

Health

Science

Tech

Home

Food

Business

Insurance

Compare Anything ››

vs.

Ethics vs. Morals

Diffen › English Language › Grammar › Words

Ethics and morals relate to “right” and “wrong” conduct. While they are sometimes used interchangeably, they are different: ethics refer to rules provided by an external source, e.g., codes of conduct in workplaces or principles in religions. Morals refer to an individual’s own principles regarding right and wrong.

Comparison chart

Ethics versus Morals comparison chart

EthicsMoralsWhat are they? The rules of conduct recognized in respect to a particular class of human actions or a particular group or culture.

Principles or habits with respect to right or wrong conduct. While morals also prescribe dos and don'ts, morality is ultimately a personal compass of right and wrong.

Where do they come from? Social system - External

Individual - Internal

Why we do it? Because society says it is the right thing to do.

Because we believe in something being right or wrong.

Flexibility Ethics are dependent on others for definition. They tend to be consistent within a certain context, but can vary between contexts.

Usually consistent, although can change if an individual’s beliefs change.

The "Gray" A person strictly following Ethical Principles may not have any Morals at all. Likewise, one could violate Ethical Principles within a given system of rules in order to maintain Moral integrity.

A Moral Person although perhaps bound by a higher covenant, may choose to follow a code of ethics as it would apply to a system. "Make it fit"

Origin Greek word "ethos" meaning"character"

Latin word "mos" meaning "custom"

Acceptability Ethics are governed by professional and legal guidelines within a particular time and place

Morality transcends cultural norms

Source of Principles

Ethics are external standards that are provided by institutions, groups, or culture to which an individual belongs. For example, lawyers, policemen, and doctors all have to follow an ethical code laid down by their profession, regardless of their own feelings or preferences. Ethics can also be considered a social system or a framework for acceptable behavior.

Morals are also influenced by culture or society, but they are personal principles created and upheld by individuals themselves.

Consistency and Flexibility

Ethics are very consistent within a certain context, but can vary greatly between contexts. For example, the ethics of the medical profession in the 21st century are generally consistent and do not change from hospital to hospital, but they are different from the ethics of the 21st century legal profession.

An individual’s moral code is usually unchanging and consistent across all contexts, but it is also possible for certain events to radically change an individual's personal beliefs and values.

Conflicts Between Ethics and Morals

One professional example of ethics conflicting with morals is the work of a defense attorney. A lawyer’s morals may tell her that murder is reprehensible and that murderers should be punished, but her ethics as a professional lawyer, require her to defend her client to the best of her abilities, even if she knows that the client is guilty.

Another example can be found in the medical field. In most parts of the world, a doctor may not euthanize a patient, even at the patient's request, as per ethical standards for health professionals. However, the same doctor may personally believe in a patient's right to die, as per the doctor's own morality.

Origins

Much of the confusion between these two words can be traced back to their origins. For example, the word "ethic" comes from Old French (etique), Late Latin (ethica), and Greek (ethos) and referred to customs or moral philosophies. "Morals" comes from Late Latin's moralis, which referred to appropriate behavior and manners in society. So, the two have very similar, if not synonymous, meanings originally.

Morality and ethics of the individual have been philosophically studied for well over a thousand years. The idea of ethics being principles that are set and applied to a group (not necessarily focused on the individual) is relatively new, though, primarily dating back to the 1600s. The distinction between ethics and morals is particularly important for philosophical ethicists.

Videos Explaining the Differences

The following video explains how ethics are objective, while morals are subjective.

References

The Definition of Morality - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Ethics Definition - Dictionary.com

Ethic Origins - Online Etymology Dictionary

Moral Origins - Wiktionary

Morals Definition - Dictionary.com

Related Comparisons

Malpractice vs Negligence

Subjective vs Objective

Affect vs Effect

Empathy vs Sympathy

Avenge vs Revenge

Principal vs Principle

Share

Follow

Cite

Share this comparison via:

If you read this far, you should follow us:

"Ethics vs Morals." Diffen.com. Diffen LLC, n.d. Web. 26 Feb 2024. < >

Comments: Ethics vs Morals

Anonymous comments (5)

October 23, 2013, 2:02pm

The Greek and Latin origins seem to indicate that the definitions are reversed. However, I think that the definitions are correct for how the terms are used. For example, Olympic athletes have a code of ethics to which they must adhere; and people are often given the advice to "follow their moral compass"

— 72.✗.✗.224

June 25, 2012, 6:43pm

WOW!!! Neat website... I love it! :D

— 70.✗.✗.68

May 30, 2013, 11:41pm

I think the distinction drawn here is backwards. If you listen to how these words are used idiomatically, moral tends to relate to codified societal beliefs that are received on an unquestioned basis (the 1960's use of the term "moral majority" for instance.) On the other hand ethics implies a philosophical and hence reasoned set of values that the individual thinks through (going back to Aristotle's Ethics).

— 173.✗.✗.75

November 15, 2013, 8:17pm

Part of being an educated person is that you know how to find the field that studies the thing you are interested in. Philosophy is the field that studies ethics. Philosophers use the terms "ethical" and "moral" more or less interchangeably, and tend not to use the term "morals".

The content here is of very very poor quality, and looks like it was simply made up by someone.

If you want to learn about this, a good starting point is the Stanford Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. That is a very high quality source, with several entries on ethics.

— 75.✗.✗.251

March 23, 2014, 12:59am

Morality is an individual's opinion of right and wrong. An ethical code is the opinion of a group that has the authority to force others to follow their views, or be penalized. Having the authority to make rules does not make your rules any more objective or rational. ALL moral views are subjective. Posting videos from a cult that believes in magic destroys your credibility.

— 76.✗.✗.223

Related Comparisons

Malpractice vs NegligenceSubjective vs ObjectiveAffect vs EffectEmpathy vs SympathyAvenge vs RevengePrincipal vs Principle"I'm Sorry" vs "I apologize"

Contribute to Diffen

Edit or create new comparisons in your area of expertise.

Log in »

Malpractice vs Negligence

Subjective vs Objective

Affect vs Effect

Empathy vs Sympathy

Avenge vs Revenge

Principal vs Principle

About Diffen

How to Cite

Log in / Register

Request a Comparison

Submit Feedback

Stay connected

© All rights reserved.

Terms of use | Privacy policy